« Posts by alex

rule #1 of business (and life)

Do not try to change people’s behaviors.

(Don’t base your business or inter-personal relationships on trying to get people to change).

The Confusing Junk of Modernism: How Duchamp isn’t an Artist

In Cabinet Magazine, issue 27, there is an article titled Readymade Remade about Pierre Pinoncelli who first made a big name for himself by pissing in Marcel Duchamp’s readymade urinal. The article examines Pinoncelli’s argument that he was bringing history and value to the urinal by doing so. While the French gov’t did not agree with Pinoncelli at all, especially after Pinoncelli pissed in the same urinal again in 2006 — the article decidedly agrees with Pinoncelli. The writer, Leland de la Durantaye, smartly cites Duchamp himself as the authority — Duchamp, after “defacing” the Mona Lisa, claims that his Mona Lisa is not a readymade. Rather this remade Mona Lisa is an “assisted readymade”. By taking mass produced art and introducing “a unique commentary”, Duchamp means to bring this item back into the spectrum of art. With this, Durantaye implies that Pinoncelli is right in his claim that the French gov’t is wrong — but then after fining Pinoncelli, should the French gov’t pay him the money? After all, Pinoncelli’s “unique commentary” has increased the value of this French treasure by taking a mass produced readymade which has “lost [its] readymade authenticity, [its] unique identity, and [. . .] dynamically infus[ing] one of the replicas with [authenticity]”.

Pinoncelli's Duchamp's Urinal

Twice stained, thrice as valuable. Look up Pierre Pinoncelli on the internet. You'll see he's quite a pissant. HA HA HA!!

Besides the “unique critique” of Duchamp’s work (of which Pinoncelli is a decidedly excited fan) there are three possible directions for contradictions:

1) Durantaye takes for granted the implication that what is valuable in art is expressed monetarily.

2) Benjamin’s famous essay on Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction equates uniqueness with art — that mass produced copies only accentuate the value of “originals” which the elite can then possess as being art. By unifying Duchamp’s readymade and his assisted readymade, Durantaye implies that Duchamp is not producing art at all — if a readymade meant to be art can be in need of “assistance” to rejoin the status of art then Duchamp is not at all an artist for Duchamp is not producing art.

3) Simultaneously, as you can imagine, Pinoncelli’s urine was cleaned from the “defaced” readymade. Nonetheless, Pinoncelli left, in the language of Lacan, an unseen stain, on that particular readymade. The British have recognized this readymade as being more intrinsically valuable. One of the subtexts of this article is that what is valuable is not necessarily tangible… that art itself has moved beyond the realm of pretty pictures and skillful techniques (for what kind of technique has Pinoncelli, besides the admirable ability to urinate in public before the eyes of others? — no doubt a feat most of us could not accomplish).

Taken all at once, although somewhat contradictory, we come across a paradox. Art then, in the contemporary age, is what both unique, intangible and monetarily valuable. Of course no matter what the French gov’t thought, they could not allow anyone pissing on any art. Imagine if they awarded Pinoncelli? What kind of people would go to the museums in the hopes of making “readymade” money? At once we see that art cannot be what is tangible. Of course, tangibility may be our best claim to any sort of possession of it. We go to museums to see art, but in fact run abut something else. So is art tangible?

If it is only tangible then Duchamp is not an artist. If it is intangible, then Duchamp and Pinoncelli are both artists. Durantaye sides with Pinoncelli and Pinoncelli with Duchamp.

But if art is not material, then what is art? If Duchamp is not an artist but a “materialist contextualist” then how are we to approach material context? We all understand that art can be horribly elitist, but is it so only in order to promote/protect its own value? Does this then make the lives of our celebrities art? What about expensive, corporate, buildings? What then happens to punk and the D.I.Y. culture? Is that no longer art but just noise (since anyone can punk)?

Again the direction seems to lie more with Deleuze and Guattari’s how more than the what. While both of these thinkers equate art with concept, if we take this discussion seriously it seems that art lies more with social positioning than anything else: architecture must be valuable because of the resources taken to produce it, as are museum housed works — and the millions of punk fans world-wide.

This bodes woe for fans of Kristeva, and all the art lovers around… as well as Deleuze and Guattari’s book What is Philosophy. But that’s the one book of theirs that I do not like. So that’s fine by me.  (Any “commentary” I would like to share on that book?  I think not, at least, I can’t comment if you’re watching…)

Me, personally? I don’t believe in any of what I just wrote anyhow.
Is that tangible enough for ya?

Beyond Existentalism

it occurs to me two implications of the previous entry one existentialism:

http://sulphuroxide.com/2011/02/22/meaning-in-the-face-of-annihilation/

1) that if meaning only works for one’s self, there isn’t any reason to respect anyone else’s mental capacities or conclusions, except for purposes of “living together”. in cases where more authoritarian minded individuals would think things like ‘single mothers are bad for society’ ( http://www.npr.org/2011/02/24/134031175/For-Single-Mothers-Stigma-Difficult-To-Shake ) there’s really no reason to respect anyone else’s life choices, or life situations… the same goes for gay marriage and homosexual relationships wherein concerned individuals would deem others as being in ways that detrimentally affect them even while more libertarian or liberal proponents would claim that such adult relationships fall under rubric of ‘no one’s business but the parties involved’…

2) nonetheless, for these reasons, existentialism does not have any strong role in politics.

while i adhere strongly to the ‘meaning is ultimately meaningless’ camp — i’m not sure where else to go with this. in the past few weeks ive been sliding really close to vulgar marxism… where questions of beauty and aesthetics become less relevant… simply because of how these problems are defined (up in the air, too, vapid and ‘feel good’…). at the same time though, especially in practice with web development (as the most obvious case) beautiful code — aesthetically pleasing algorithms and presentation — remain at the forefront of my conditions for a project that is more ‘completed’. this is a definite issue, to put it bluntly, at the onset, a huge contradiction.

i think this ‘huge problem’ that i have is very similar to more traditional philosophies (of which i think i draw a large part from)… namely the differences between idealism and physicalism… the lines are badly drawn (imho) because it’s not so much the mentalists vs the physicalists… but really a difference between “ontology” and “ontic” or design and economics. zizek fielded this area strongly with this back in ticklish subject although I must say that by parallax gap, he may have resolved it enough in his head that the question is buried but never fully addressed anymore but as a more general debate… i don’t know i havent read any zizek recently…

a more pragmatic approach can be found within the debate between urban designers on the point of view of ‘good design’ vs ‘economic business plans’– neither of which by itself, are always what’s best for neighborhoods. the quote froms directly from this discussion, and it’s eloquently put by mariela alfonzo
you can catch the link here: http://www.publicprivatepassion.com/2011/02/can-cities-take-stand-on-good-urban.html

Ultimately, the bottom line is you cannot reach a compromise between urban design and economic development – that’s a losing battle. I firmly believe you need the former to achieve the latter, but you have to understand the latter when devising the former. We HAVE to stop looking at “design” as a line item within the “costs” section of a pro-forma.

the company apple masters these principles with their slick ipod, and iphone designs… and while they do not have market dominance wen it comes to the cell phone industry, they are industry leaders.  if you apply this ‘solution’ analogously to philosophy then you get that meaning, in order to be more than an existential statement of how one navigates — in order to be ‘meaningful’, it must also be epistemologically sophisticated in how one interfaces with their situation, to put it in a smarmy but ‘duhh’ kind of way. so as far as politics go, we can’t be sophists… and we can’t be arrogantly totalitarian, but at the same time, we need to reify our problems. we must be sophisticated in the deleuze and guattari way via concepts — we must seek to address problems that are critically problems — in how those structural crises make a real impact. we can’t address all problems that we find — because many of them are not really meaningful problems.

how we separate this, between what is meaningful and what is not, throws us back quite a few steps. the ‘corporate’ response would be to define the problem in a tangible metric… so that we can attain that goal. which of course, would please stock holders, give us a strong sense of progress… but this ‘solution’ by itself also did cause the stock crises of our current day. we do also need to keep in the big picture as well. which is a problem, because tactically we have ‘solutions’ which cannot be ‘solutions’ in an open-ended undefined system.

you realize that philosophy as a whole works best when it abstracts/extracts meaning from complexity.  it reduces phenomenon the way language names things, the way we put new information, new items we encounter into old files.  so philosophy, and a systems approach can best work at giving us tools to handle past situations.  it can ‘predict’ previous events accurately because the relationships which were relevant at the time of philosophizing were — relevant.  things change, and sometimes those events don’t work no more — the indexes have been re-shuffled so a system may not predict anything much anymore.  i think this is where the quote above (from an urban planner on the relationship between ‘good’ urban design and ‘productive’ economic plans) applies.  the various ‘schools’ are great, because they have focused on their limited scope questions on real world situations.  we’ve gotten so in-depth!  but that depth is narrowly defined and runs the risk of becoming a kind of art-for-artists.  in order to make great statements that shake up those studies AND make them accessible for outsiders, we need genius,  we need something new and fresh to break out of old paradigms.

believe it or not, the bloggers from the havard business review all echo the same issues.  in a world of structured relations, structured cash flow, marketing plans and business plans… urban planning and a SYSTEMS approach, we need what they call ‘innovation’ — part of the key in many of their posts is a kind of ‘how to break out of our mold’.  if existentialism as a philosophy only works for one’s own meaning — how we connect with others, how we expressedly cross the gaps in this field becomes a matter of innovation and creativity.  after all, getting stuck in one’s head is like starting a college in academia. to use a classic example, do neurologists and cognitive psychologists talk to one another?

to use the quote above as an analogy, to use effective communication requires that we understand the mindset of the one we speak to and our own mindset.  both need to inform each other, which means of course, a transdisciplinary approach. (again, DUHH).  how descartes has problems with this, stems from how he defines the mind as a closed system.  well guess what, our minds ARE closed systems in so far as we think about them as such… they obviously still manage to create objects and process new information in astonishingly innovative ways.

where this happens at the subterranean level, is of course, what deleuze and guattari call rhizomes.

how we facilitate and actively push for those connections is what i call rhizomatic architecture. ITS NOT JUST ABOUT TREES (aborescence), BABY!

Meaning in the Face of Annihilation

A few days ago, I was showing houses to an old friend who is now a client. It was raining and we had passed by a smaller duplex. The pictures on the MLS aren’t the same as seeing the context of the property with your own eyes. After seeing it, he decided he didn’t want to gos in and disturb the people in there. There are better deals around. We were talking about life in general — catching up as it were — since we hadn’t really talked in a long time. In showing houses, you inevitably turn towards the topic of the future. Let’s call this future-talk.

Future-talk is odd, it’s not often grounded in the present even though we talk about the future by way of the things we do during the present. But sometimes it is, and you can see that doesn’t just contain hopes and dreams that people have for the future. The future often also contains a justification of the present (current actions, current statuses &c). The present then, acts like a bridge that links the past and the future… even though it’s really disjunct (the present belongs to neither past nor future). And yet, looking for a home does this past-present-future connection quite well. People who want to buy a home, who have money are serious. It’s not chump change to drop close to half a million… It’s something to want a place to call your own, to START A FAMILY

What people want in a home is about as important as who they are, and what their priorities are. Buying a house, even as an investment, represents a whole-lotta-commitment, (in a Led Zeppelin kind of way) and as old friends we were genuinely interested in what the other was doing. This is the best kind of relationship building anyway, and the best sales people do it well. They are interested and understand their client — at least they can appear to be to the client. And that’s what’s important, to orient yourself. Not just what the inside of the house looks like (which is where most of us see the house anyway)… but also the outside, the kind of neighborhood, the people, the schools, the local businesses, if we can see our parents coming over (or not), or friends… in American Literature, the home is a very important character. It’s kind of like the over-shadow, even if the home is also the town… where someone runs from, or runs to… And in that way it acts much like how God acts for people’s lives. It orients them, it becomes an attractor (or repellent)…

So fast forward a bunch of particulars, when we got back into my car, he asked me if I believed in God.

Now I don’t know what he thinks, and I didn’t ask — but I told him, yes I believe I do. Although if most people ask me if I do, I usually say No because if I say Yes, then I appear to be very misleading. The fact is, what I am thinking of in my head probably in no way resembles what they are thinking of when they mention God..

This needs elaboration so I said very directly, I don’t really believe in the supremacy of a particular entity, per se, at least not one that is separate or dis-contiguous from everything else. I also don’t believe that I am (or that human beings are) central to the workings of the universe or that my actions (or that human actions) have any centrality to what’s actually going on. The universe is indifferent.

My friend then said, Yes, that’s really not in agreement with most people.

I also added I don’t believe that the meaning in my head has any bearing whatsoever on the universe at all. Meaning makes no difference to anyone except myself and vis versa.

A good short article on the uncentrality of Das Sein can be read by Paul Graham. He wrote an essay called See Randomness. I realize now, after I’ve put it in here, that the article itself exists in a vacuum much unlike future-talk and houses but very much like the present. In other words, this article does not attempt to bridge any kind of relationship with a point of view that we are in fact central to the universe, or that the meaning we take for granted is inscripted in the very core of the universe. Rather Graham argues for consideration of alternate understandings of events. He grounds his appeal for personal distance on an evolutionary foundation — that our ‘identity’ of a cohesive, rational self is an indeterminate fiction — that we should not take central our own needs and desires when orienting the ‘meaning’ of the things that happen around us. He would agree with me then, that meaning is the way each of us navigates what would otherwise be ‘randomness’. This meaning is not a universal principle in which our suffering or joy has any bearing in the cogs of the cosmic machine. Our suffering or joy is, rather neutral, much like how chemical reactions are neutral.

Gilles Deleuze in Practical Philosophy wrote very elegantly on this topic. I read his book twice to understand how he dismantles notions of ontology and instead recombines (and yet includes them) from a ground floor up so that they retain their parts, their sums, essences, attributions and conjugations. The first reading only served to confuse me, as the orientation wasn’t around a metaphyics of presence even while he preserves ‘essence’ as a central mode of anchoring meaning. The difference lies in the supposition that essence is constructed as “a relation of reciprocity” even while “Essence — Necessarily constitutes the essence of a thing …, a thing can neither be nor be conceived without, and vise versa, what can neither be conceived without the thing” (64). See how Deleuze has his cake and eats it too? Essence is the thing and the thing, essence. Likewise, what overrides the interactions of what we would understand both in a physical and a mental way is abstracted as a neturality of the interplay of relations — the exposition of Spinozan Ethics — without consciousness as being at all primary. In fact, it’s closer to epiphenomenalism if anything, although what Deleuze does does not push a metaphysics of presence of anything, nor does it sustain that heavy mutuality of dualism…

When a body ‘encounters’ another body, or an idea another idea, it happens that the two relations sometimes combine to form a more powerful whole, and sometimes one decomposes the other, destroying the cohesion of its parts. This is what is prodigious in the body and the mind alike, these sets of living parts that enter into composition with and decompose one another according to complex laws. The order of causes is therefore an order of composition and decomposition of relations, which infinitely affects all of nature. But as conscious beings, we ever apprehend anything but the effects of these compositions and decompositions: we experience joy when a body encounters ours and enters into composition with it, and sadness when, on the contrary, a body or an idea threaten our own coherence. [. . .] In short, the conditions under which we know things and are conscious of ourselves condemn us to have only inadequate ideas, ideas that are confused and mutilated, effects separated from their real causes. That is why it is scarcely possible to think that little children are happy, or that the first man was perfect: ignorant of causes and natures, reduced to the consciousness of events, condemned to undergo effects, they are slaves of everything, anxious and unhappy, in proportion to their imperfection. (19)

I believe that to most people who would orient themselves (or at least humanity) in the universe, and understand that there is an intrinsic place for them, for an I to wait and stand in luxury, as the children of the universe — either in this life or the next. I suspect that many of us feel (even if we know otherwise) that we are some how important — or that we are somehow deserving of all good things. So many of us, after Deleuze’s reading may feel that this point of view is horrible burden. Without that grounding of I or even God, there is no reason for anyone to behave or be good. Without God, many would insist that we get ultimate freedom but you also get ultimate responsibility. The universe won’t take care to preserve you, or transmogrify you based on karma… It is as though, without a direct core to the center of the universe, we should all eat each other and be terrified that others can do to us as they will.

Many thinkers and writers have written that exposure to the Scared Other, Big Other, the Eagle are all terrifying experiences that would destroy small others like ourselves. To experience God, as it were, is to become annihilated. I don’t believe this to be the case though. Yitz Jacob who ponders the mystic musings in the Jewish tradition has a particularly applicable story here about one’s relation with the Sacred Other on Heaven and on Earth. The point of the story then, I think, has to do with being able to relate to HaShem, which is easy in Heaven but not so much on Earth. While being stifled on a “Heaven that sees all” makes much sense to me, the radical view that our essentiality is not at all cohesive (that we disintegrate) when faced with the Cohesion of the Almighty jumps too far. Now, Jacob does not claim we disintegrate in his blog post, but he does note that when in Heaven, everything is visible — by this, I took it to mean that HaShem is visible too. And if God is apparent then it also becomes very apparent what we should do. This doesn’t necessarily mean we don’t exist in Heaven, but it does mean that we lose our free will.

I am not so sure that is the case. After all, should not the Cohesion of the Almighty must in fact include the cohesion of all our little partial essentialities as well? So it’s not so much that without God we get everything. Rather, it’s with God that everything is allowed.

Fyodor Dostoevsky in The Brothers Karamazov explores this topic through Ivan Karamazov — this is related to Ivan’s struggle. The brunt of it is that only with God can we have anything — only with God is everything allowed. The naked weight is that God is necessary — He does define for us what is allowed, but only because without God we would be an indistinguishable mass from everything else. Ivan, ever so rational, insists on the sheer the perversity of human beings that the Devil is made from Man’s image even though a God may or may not exist. I don’t know who Dostoevsky found inspirational enough to create a character like Ivan from, but I do feel that Ivan is under-developed. Ivan’s main source of torture is that he isn’t sure if there is a God or not — he seems to think there isn’t actually a God because of the vast cruelties that people play on one another — because bad people get away with so much! Ivan is getting two things confused though. Ivan continues to serve in a religious institution, so not believing in God is a terrible burden for him. Nonetheless Ivan sees the reasoning for expressing a belief in God — unity and singularity in the physical sense, not withstanding, but also for human society. People need God. People need to be put into their place — his poem ‘The Grand Inquisitor’ uses the tools of the Devil to do the work of God. And it’s through the Devil that the goodness of God can become apparent… that we then can see that we do have a choice. God becomes then, a field that anchors it all, Devil, God, everything. This field contains everything actual and anything possible — while containing an inscripted navigation as to what is good and right for people.

So to go back to Deleuze, what is right and good for people as a society is what mutually increases their power — what allows them to coexist in harmony. It is of no small coincidence then, that this relationship is much like the Cohesion of the Almighty. On the one hand, the big picture is necessary — for us to be one, but to ride upon the Law and live it to its fullest extent would force us to lose our ability to have freedom. To use Jacob’s parable, the Earth is curved so we can’t tell what’s all around us — so we can do what we like, in a limited scope — even if it is to make mistakes. It’s only in the firmament where we can see all around, and experience the full blunt of it. Keeping the big picture in mind is difficult — as material creatures we are made to get what we can now, enjoy ourselves and satisfy immediate urges. Why wait? We don’t know what will happen to us next! So we end up with conflicting behavior that satisfies one aspect of our person but not another or we short ourselves in the long run for short term gain… and where does meaning fit into this?

Meaning fits into everything as the justifications, explanations, short-circuits in our daily lives that smoothen over the otherwise random assortment of information that would bombard us, distract us, vex us or otherwise provoke perhaps too much uncertainty in our lives. If we were terribly uncertain, it’s doubtful we would ever have children, or ever buy a house, or ever do anything. If we didn’t think we could finish what we wanted to do then most of us would probably never do it. I believe meaning is the tactical moves that assure us coherency in our personal internal lives.

In other words, meaning isn’t the inner workings of physics or math, or biology. The knowledge of science explores actual relations, insofar as we can test them. But that’s not meaningful. Rocks are not meaningful. Plants are not meaningful. Being alive is not meaningful. Being alive is biological. Evolution is not meaningful. The movie A Serious Man, one of my favorite movies, explores this issue. Larry Gopnik understands the math that he teaches in his class but he does not understand the story behind Schrödinger’s cat. He is always caught up in a series of diversions, wondering what the ‘truth’ behind any event is. Knowing or not knowing the truth is not important — the Coen brothers continually sink us into ambiguity, delay our reception of what anyone actually means or the actual intent of any character’s action. Gopnik then gets caught up in how that ‘truth’ of anything is both hidden and not at all meaningful. He can’t ever decide what he wants because he thinks he needs to know ‘what the intent of everything’ must be before he can figure out what he should want. It drives him to the brink, where he comes speechless, and only stares ahead.

This is very much the serious philosopher’s problem is. We think that the universe should somehow have a place for us, that what we want should somehow be apparent to us, written for us in the stars, in our surroundings, in life. We may come some day to understand how life works, how to stop death, how to create beauty and art — these things may become possible through science. But that kind of knowledge isn’t meaningful because it won’t tell us how to live or deal with all things personal.

This means then, that meaning is not universal. Meaningfulness is for US… each of us… independent of one another. It makes sense then, that our mental worlds are coexistent but also incompossible — that a gull of incommensurable, indefinite and indeterminate difference separates one mind from another … and that we aren’t privy to one another’s minds… even if we are all ‘made the same way’. We aren’t made to read each other’s minds. It would be bad for us if everyone else could read our mind… because we would be manipulated and abused. Our individual survival would be uncertain… yet ironically, as humans we are incredibly social and we DO need each other. Together we are strong. Under an Almighty, we are all the more Mighty. As a society, we do need those ‘universal’ inscriptions that having a God would define for us. It’s just that, while there is always a Big Other in any human culture who judges each of us small others (even if it is a reciprocity such as the Asian notion of ‘face’) only the Judeo-Christian-Islam traditions so directly gave Him a Voice, or should I say, the Word. And it seems that traditions in this tradition, such as Protestants, so individuated this Word so that it wasn’t a complex system like Confucianism or the Hindi-castes, but rather it was tied to a single soul, for each of us, waiting for us to become ripe, to gain awareness of it.

And that’s where I can’t follow. Personally, that’s too much like a road written in the firmament (although to some it isn’t…). To project such a path seems to me to prompt a kind of Lacanian hysteria — much like Star Trek — we would zip around the universe looking for something but not knowing what. On the one hand then, Protestants, especially Puritans, have a very dour outlook. They are serious. And now, we get to the most deadly of future-talks. After all, everything, all responsibility for their own relationship with God rests on their shoulders. What about their past? Their present? Their future? It’s all written in the sky. Without that relationship with God, there can only be nothing. But now that I wrote this, I don’t think that responsibility rests only with Puritans… In any group, understanding how responsibility is divided is important; be it on an individual, a family or a collective of some sort, any group needs its members to be responsive in a way that is coherent. I suppose though, by separating any kind of Word from meaning means I am writing this entry as a philosophical dead-end. There is neither impetus nor universal appeal because this kind of meaning is too individual. (It is, after all, one philosopher can hardly talk to another!) Nonetheless, what I have put here works for me (at least now)… although it is written mostly as a universal statement about human kind.

Perhaps ironically, as such a ‘universal’ statement, it must encapsulate an unnavigable void and include other minds… even though this statement most likely, is not meaningful for you.

Yet at the same time, it becomes a very special thing, when a home speaks to you about your future.

on Testing Cheetos in Soviet Unterzoegersdorf

Economics and market behavior is a huge area of study — the best business minds are all interested in it — so rather than try and make an exhaustive account, I would like to point to one particular event.

A northern European group that started off making fictional zines and theorizing on ‘happenings’ called monochrom created a few years ago a last bastillion of Soviet culture called Soviet Unterzoegersdorf.  What started out as a village in the Austrian countryside ‘remade’ into the last Soviet Country (with tours available) became so widely popular that monochrom could not in good conscience continue to give tours.  Having three times the population of a 500 people village swamp the village for a weekend would be potentially devastating.  Eventually, in order to further the experience, monochrom created an ‘adventure style’ video game.  I won’t go into detail about the game here, what I am more interested in is how this experience interfaced with the economy.

It seems that with capitalism, we desire experiences, the novel experiences things can give us. There are plenty of Marxist thought about this — but what is interesting, although perhaps difficult to assess is how these novel experiences become translatable into other Cultures, of other peoples, and even of one’s past cultural experiences — which become commodified into a new kind of hybrid experience entirely, neither of the past nor of our ‘normal’ experience, but wholly of the present.

Monochrom went on to have various installations such as the Unterzoegersdorf computer (which ran on a coal furnace one had to shovel continuously in order for another person to be able to play Tetris) as well as various Unterzoegersdorf installations.  There was one especially interesting moment when they were kicked out of a computer convention as the Unterzoegersdorf representative with the Unterzoegersdorf camera man was borderline-trolling party-goers, perhaps offensive to Disney officials running the convention.  The Unterzoegersdorf representative also, for purposes of art, had the wild experience of eating a glob of wasabe ‘not knowing what wasabe is… and deciding that it was capitalist posion’.  Of course, one assumes the Unterzoegersdorf camera man was using a modern camera, something the Unterzoegersdorf representative did not even seem to notice as being astounding.

One particular event they did was particular applicable to this discussion.  The website boing boing hired Monochrom to do a viral video for Cheetos, paying them a sum of a few thousand dollars.  Monochrom saw a prime opportunity to further explore capitalist relationships with their very anti-capitalist characters.  The results are below.  I invite you to take the time to watch all 6 segments.  It is delightful.

Unterzoegersdorf/Cheetos Campaign

While amusing, one cannot help but think that the compete rage of the Soviet Unterzoegersdorf characters, in part jest, at being ‘tricked’ and ‘used’ to promote a very Capitalist-foodstuff but in part seriousness — for Unterzoegersdorf-ians to find their livelihood but a ‘colony’ of the Global Economy.  While Cheetos is featured heavily in the dialogue as the center of conflict, the nature of the Monochrom’s tension is more on the side of Unterzoegersdorf-ians trying to figure out what to make of the raw junk of Capitalism.  It may benefit Cheetos only to be repeatedly mentioned and pondered — we laugh because the weird orange coloring DOES smear all over our hands.  In fact, we are reminded of Cheetos and that may be enough to make our mouth water (or wince) in association.  Larger questions remain largely unexamined What should we make of our own economic proliferation?  How should we come to terms with ourselves?  In an exploration of Unterzoegersdorf we come to face ourselves as Other — perhaps in what only great works of Art do — reflected back to ourselves our own values in negativity, as dissymmetry and excess, the best non-linguistic analysis of all, something even Emmanuel Levinas refuses to see — when he preaches of the acceptance of the Other but cannot accept those ‘asiatic hordes’ which surround Israel… and refuses to deal with them as citizens of humanity…

I’d hate to think that if I were to continue on and on, I would end up swallowing myself into a Hegelian synthesis of some sort, negative and particular made universal, more or less.

I also strikes me that this entry is applicable with the previous On Testing IRL although creating such a viral meme does not in fact have a control group of any sort. One is immediately hypnotized in Soviet Unterzoegersdorf our own image, as fascist as they are in our unthinking allegiance to our own ideology, something which accepts Cheetos as blindly as they reject it.

on Testing IRL

So I did join Ramit Sethi’s earn1k insider’s list.

It’s quite interesting to note how often he responds to objects and naysayers about his product. Of course he’s right — if you can’t spare 30 minutes from your day to save you potentially hours then you’re wasting time by even considering throwing 1k into a program on how to improve… (business practice, marketing, negotiation skills…). Most of his regular emails seem composed of this kind of hustle, to urge people to get off their butts and refuse mediocrity.

This is good because often many of my closest friends, while all intelligent and capable, do not invest their time into activities that will benefit them in the long run. Video games are the best time-waster. You spend 40 or 60 bucks to buy a game and then spend the next week or two playing it and beating it. It’s good to spend 12 hours, say on Ico or 115 hours on GTA4 and then go to bed at night feeling like you’ve made progress. You have made progress. It’s just not applicable to life. It’s the same thing with wildly successful multi-player games like Left 4 Dead, Battle Field 2142 or Call of Duty 4. Yes I’ve played most of these games (except Ico). And I’ve not beaten a single one of them. But the online games are especially trying because you do cooperate with other people, or play against them, and you get players who take them way too seriously. Any sense of accomplishment from a video game is real — even if the accomplishment and the work never fully or even partially translate into a real life benefit. Unlike say, climbing a corporate ladder or learning a new trade… So the email urging is good. People are hooked in some sense, many many people. And it’s good to call people out — the ones who would set goals for themselves but never follow through… because the goals are only there for them to remind themselves that they aren’t as loserly as anyone else… (I find that so annoying, to have a ‘serious’ conversation with someone who believes they will do something but never do it!) So I do agree with Ramit on this.

But at the same time it’s freak’n annoying. I didn’t realize that reading his emails would mean that I would get badgered into doing whatever he wanted me to do. Taking action right away, or at least within a reasonable time frame. That’s okay though, because if it’s annoying enough I could always unsubscribe. But I won’t because I do find value in what he says, even if most of his emails is him responding to whining (he must get alot of people who reply with whining).

Anyway, I’m starting to ramble but I did look at Ramit’s offering of a 60 minute interview with Tim Ferris on the subject of testing. They are about the same age I am, and they speak of testing as Testing. I listened to the interview while I was writing some database code for MySql and while answering some emails on a Saturday afternoon. The subject of testing is interesting, although I kind of wished they had set the foundation for it better.

In my work-life I don’t have much guidance as to how to go about conducting business. Since my services are relatively new on the market (as a niche business), testing is necessary for me. So some areas in which testing apply are in a networking situation, saying different things for the breakfast 30 second microphone time — is useful. Trying out different pricing, and trying to see what fits best is another thing I’ve done. Asking customers and potential clients how we may better service their needs, also works. Ferris had some interesting and useful comments about testing (for instance don’t test when the risk is too high). Perhaps I am too new to Ramit’s blog — because I am not certain what the context is for testing. For instance, when is it good to test? The interview seems to conclude that testing is always good — when the risks are not too high. I guess this is alright, but I think at some point, testing becomes trolling. In real life or online.

How do you know what to test? Going back to the video game scenario, people ‘test’ the rules in video games all the time. For instance, in the original Battlefield 1942 people learned that they can put the engineer bombs into a jeep and drive it into a tank, effectively destroying the tank with a car bomb. That’s testing but the rewards are so low… and transitory. Owning on an online server might be great if you are 14, but it’s less relevant if you’re 25 or even 35… Social ‘situations’ online such as on discussion forum don’t seem like a good place to ‘test’ although asking people their opinions on things is less a test than just surveying… (this is where I disagree with their notion of testing, although its vaguely applicable). If anything, determining when to test seems like a matter of boredom or curiosity. Ultimately, doing website SEO requires some kind of testing — to find out one’s target market or to find out which words are the ones which best attract customer dollars (if it is indeed that kind of website). So testing as an effective activity really depends on the context of what’s really at stake. When does testing become less effective and more about provoking people for whatever reaction they get?

If anything, the most useful point about testing is more about how to determine when we need to test something. It’s obvious when we aren’t getting results at all or if we don’t have enough information to make a decision that we need to expand out knowledge base. The best way to do that is to test new situations. But it becomes less obvious if we are succeeding that we need to test if we are to maximize or improve what we want to do. Life is (often but not always) about learning new things. If we are complacent, satisfied with what we have, or afraid of losing — then testing becomes less important. Likewise, how we can step outside of our normal processes and conceive of a new way of doing things — paradigm shift or whatever you want to call it — is a completely different topic in itself, one that has had many many books written about it. In fact, such a level of creative-stepping-outside-of-the-proverbial-box is the wet dream of many many scientists, writers, managers, marketers, CEOs… and of course all those really smart finance people who create new finance instruments for investors all the time.

So figuring out how to test or construct new paradigms or ‘scripts’ as Ramit calls them, may be beyond the scope of this entry, even if that’s what I’m talking about. In fact, the other side of testing is the purpose of testing — at least in business — and that’s INNOVATION.

Recently Harvard Business Review Blogs have got some interesting thoughts on INNOVATION. Two of the three articles they have relate to the topic of testing. For instance, Quicky is an open-source model for product innovation, created by users to try and make better products. In essence, the users themselves were suggesting what they would like to buy. That certainly circumvents normal business ‘testing’. Of greater relevance, though, is this entry on Google’s attempt at being innovative — which basically could be resolved if Google were to test its innovations before committing to creating them. This is a clear case where testing is necessary.

In general, testing isn’t just about originating a new idea and seeing if it will fly, it’s about interacting in the field of interest — succeeding where you want to succeed and trying new things to mark out territory for proposed behavior.

On this vein, it may be of greater interest to introduce someone who has built a career off of testing (social boundaries) — and then publicizing it for all to gawk at… Would Ramit interview Tucker Max about testing and how he determines what next to test or how he goes about ‘testing’? (Who knows, maybe he already has! I just started reading the Ramit’s blog, but I don’t read Tucker’s…)

*note, bringing up the two of them yet again seems kind of nefarious, or atleast it feels that way to me, but I think relevant because their models of interaction seem so similar… it may be interesting to see if Tucker Max can engage on the level of discourse Ramit seems so bent on focusing… and what he might be able to say… if it would even be relevant at all. It is of note though that Ramit did mention pick up artists I haven’t listened to this pod cast, but I did read the entry. Ramit’s main criticism about PUA is that it’s more about scoring than less about personal self-development… I don’t know… do you think Tucker Max is about personal self-development? It seems to me that he is about some kind of development… although it’s quite unclear what.

on Inscripting Meaning into the Universal Void

This is why I would miss Dave if something ever happened to him.

I don’t get this level of conversation with anyone else.

In case you can’t tell from these first four lines, I’m going to try and write this out in a different way.

I was at the gym about two weeks ago with him. Immediately after checking in at the counter I picked a random topic of conversation I found interesting.

“Dave! You know that some astrologers up in Minnesota have decided that there are 13 astrology signs?” (link here 13 Astrology signs due to Alteration in Earths Rotation)

Dave did not say anything so I continued. (I know he does not care about astrology at all.)

“So, I told *** that according to the new astrology she’s not really a Scorpio — she’s really a Virgo. And that her kids were actually Sagittarians. She disagreed. I told her that this was a ‘typical virgo-trait’. She then told me that this new astrology sucked and that she could strangle me. Then I told **** that she that we weren’t really virgos but a leos. She said it was only for people born after 2009. Maybe that’s really true but I disagreed. Then I said it was retroactive and she called shenanigans. Then I told ***** that she wasn’t really a Capricorn, but actually a sag. And you know what she said?”

“What?”

“She said ‘ooh, so that’s why my horoscope never matched.’ Haha, it only didn’t work on *****. Astrological-trolling.”

By this time we were sitting at a chest weight machine. We put some weights on and without discussing it were starting to take turns.

Dave: “You know, Alex, this actually makes me really angry.”

“Why?”

Dave: “Because it’s so stupid. Astrology isn’t real. Why should they care about what astrological sign they have? It’s completely irrational.”

“What does it matter? It’s a filter, an arbitrary way of assigning meaning.”

“But it’s not true! Religion is the opiate of the masses.”

This is something we’ve discussed many times. “So? The meaning is what’s true, not the specificity of the actually sign-ology. You may not think that there is a God but you don’t know that. It’s what’s on South Park, that episode about Mormons. It may all be just untrue but it helps people live in a good and upstanding way.”

Dave: “You know, I used to work with a co-worker back at ********** and we would talk about this.” I got onto the machine. “I asked him once, what if you found irrefutable evidence that God was not real. No one knew you had this evidence and it was absolutely convincing. What would you do?”

“What did he say?”

Dave: “He said he would destroy the evidence. He said he would find some way to destroy it so it would be irretrievable and then he would hide the fact he ever found it.”

“He wouldn’t – He wouldn’t bring it out to other people to enlighten them? What if he was afraid of social unrest?” I got up and Dave sat in the machine.

Dave: “He said he would pretend he never found it. And I believed him. I really believed that’s what he would do.”

“Hm.” I watched Dave work the machine. While he was pumping at the machine: “But that’s what faith is.”

Dave: “But he’s being irrational. There’s no reason for him do that. Even if he didn’t want to tell anyone else, he could reform. Why believe in a myth, in an illusion?”

Dave seemed to be getting upset. I said: “There’s a fundamental flaw in what you are thinking — and it’s the opposite of what most people would think. Most people assume that there has to be a solid relationship between reality and meaning. That facts mean specific things and the presence of those items verifies a particular logic. Like everything is sensible like in CSI or in Sherlock Holmes. Most people don’t critically think either, they fit facts into a pre-ordained meaning they would like to see. For example racism as posited by Slavoj Zizek is pathological in the Kantian sense — meaning that perception and meaning tie regardless of the actuality of a situation.” I sat in the machine and in the process of pushing weights I continued to speak: “In Zizek’s example, assume that someone who was Anti-Semitic was faced with a Jew who was misery. That someone would declare, that ‘Jew is misery!’ (because he’s a Jew) and not because (he’s tight with money). You’re just taking it to the next level, that reality and meaning have to be tied together. If meaning doesn’t fit the facts then meaning should change too. The two really don’t coincide. It’s almost like saying, ‘Jews being misery is racist therefore we can never declare someone who is a Jew to also be misery… because that is also racist’.”

I was huffing when I got off and Dave sat in the seat: “There are laws to the universe. Things begin and things end.”

“Sure, so you would believe in the absent watch maker.”

Dave: “What?”

“The absent watch maker. It’s the idea from Deism in the 17th century that the universe is orderly, and that alone determines that there is a God… without religion. He set the watch rolling, disappeared and everything matched up. We all have a place in the universe, our lives have cosmological significance.”

Dave’s turn again. He increased the weights. He got back on. Dave: “This is a weighty subject matter.”

“Ha ha. Reality itself is not orderly. In fact, Lacan hit it on the head when he claimed that the Real is a miss-match of misshapen, disorderly partialities that coincide in an unrecognizable, irreconcilable manner. We each understand and attach meaning to these coincidences, create other from apparitions and claim that this has a cosmological significance that continues beyond our sight.”

Dave: “Sure reality is orderly. I like to think that the ball rolling away appears on the other side — and is the same ball.”

“Sure reality is orderly, that’s why [this gym] is playing ‘Already Gone’ by the Eagles — think that’s a coincidence? No it’s orderly! Because God is Already Gone! All we have left is a universal order WITHOUT the possibility of coincidences!

Our conversation kind of ended there because I forget what happened afterwards. But I think he got what I was saying. If you see order in some places, you might as well extend order into other areas. Without an objective measure that is universally real, there isn’t really any way of determining what should also be objective. Science is one way, but it’s based on our shared experiences, and what we can agree on as a bunch of humans.

Plus, science is out of the realm of philosophy, strictly speaking. When we start to deal with softer issues, like the indeterminateness of tribes in anthropology or ontology — items that we can’t test in an objective circumstance, we begin to lose our bearings. Never mind that science may structure technology which shapes our lives in countless fashions — for our every day human being, we exist in a personal constellation whose orientation is without any outside referents. No one knows what things mean to us, for instance. No one knows how these connections work — except for us, the subject. And so when it comes to culture we too as a society assume that certain items have a weightiness that members outside our culture would not readily attribute.

But that is how we like to fit things. We think that the role of a person in a culture is inscripted into tradition, inscripted into the universe, for time immemorial. When I got to bed in the morning, I will wake up in the same place I woke up at. And if not, then there has to be a reasonable continuity of experience that happens even if I do not directly experience it — that it is in fact experiential (by someone like me). That people are meant to be a certain way, to play certain roles. Each of us then objectively exist in universes that are incommensurably different. Descartes had this problem when he ‘Cogito Ergo Sum’med his way into two distinct substances… then was unable to not only meld the two substances of mental and physical together — but also unable to account for the fact that we while we share physical experiences with others, we don’t also share mental experiences with others in the same way as the physical realm.

If anything, what Lacan notes as being the Symbolic — that realm of meaning making — is itself the horizon of the Real, the bulwark that fends off the insecure unaccountable, ir-reasonableness of the Real. In much the same way this inability to think through facets of reality that deny cognitive metabolism can only be analogized by our continued trips to the gym… going through the pain of building up our the most ir-reasonable, silent, and unaccountable mass of dividuation1 — all for the purposes of assigning and assuring our place without the social continuity as being male, fit and buff… with all their attendant significations. — the other side of our dividuation being namely that other black mass which is our unknown inner portions of our consciousness. Our body is restless, our mind is restless. Each one prompt the other, — Act! much like the tension between personal and social determinations…

In this sense, the only universal available to us is the universal void — not the “out there” beyond the scope of our senses, but that Heideggerian “black box” of Das Sein, somewhere in the non-shape of our Cartesian soft axies of mind and body.

1 It is a split subject divided between itself and a demand that it cannot meet, a demand that makes it the subject that it is, but which it cannot entirely fulfill. From Simon Critchley

Unfolding Kandinsky: Spirituality and Expression

It took me about two years to get through most of Gilles Deleuze’s works. In that time, my understanding of Deleuze fluctuated greatly. The apex of my academic education came about when I wrote the following paper when finishing my second BA as a grad student (I had mostly completely my graduate degree. I had another a year I needed to wait because of the way my classes fell, so I decided to finish a second BA in that year.)

The following paper was written for an Art and Religion Class back in 2005. Any paper we produced as the class paper needed to involve religion (or spirituality) and art. I chose Kandinsky, because in looking at texts, I thought it would be an easier transition to write about an art’s thoughts on art than on art directly. Also, to make the paper manageable, I decided to limit the works from Deleuze to just The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque. Eventually under the same instructor (Linda Lam-Easton, who was a very unusual but extremely well crafted instructor) I audited a Taoism class which I never completed. I was going to write a paper on Taoism and Immanual Kant but never got around to it.

Anyway, I post this paper on Kandinsky here as a point of reference.

Unfolding Kandinsky: Spirituality and Expression

In Kandinsky’s first book, Concerning the Spiritual in Art, he introduces painting as a mode of spiritual expression. His focus is on how art is spiritual and how material works to influence spirit. Although he speaks at length about art in general, his main focus is on painting. When he reaches the section on painting, he claims that painting has two “weapons” (24) color and form. Perhaps because of his heavy reliance on musical examples of form, he feels it unnecessary to explore form. Instead, he examines color. Yet, the examination of color is even less useful than the aesthetic statement about spirituality in art. Even before diving into an examination of color, Kandinsky disclaims, “such definitions [of color] are not universally possible” (24). But for the remaining pages in his work, he feels it necessary to try and provide these impossible definitions. In the midst of all this, where he theorizes about the psychological develop of man and the reasons why we must paint in new ways – only “a first encounter with any new phenomenon exercises immediately an impression on the soul” (23). This first encounter is an encounter with spirit, with art. Yet in shaping his explanation, he remains limited by the classical perspective, a comment both on art and theory. While he recognizes that a certain human being sees art while other human beings see things, he still ignores the role a specifically formed subject has on painting and vis versa. In other words, he does not go far enough in his examination. Kandinsky himself realizes this, which is why he wrote a second book, Point and Line to Plane in an attempt to cover any gaps in his subject matter, not by examining color, but by examining form. This second work relies heavily on a methodology imitating science – to be objective and to master the Real by covering it up with a discourse generated by methodology. For this reason, he resists speaking of the subject and of spirituality, even as he tries to cover gaps in his first work. What is decided at the end of Kandinsky’s second book is that art relies on a projection of tension, between lines and points in order to achieve a spiritual visual space. This also assumes that such tension is innate in viewing human beings. In his first work, Kandinsky would speak of such tension as “vibrations in the soul” (24). In his second, he claims that “Art mirrors itself upon the surface of our consciousness” and that “entering art’s message [is] to experience its pulsating-life with all one’s senses” (17). How this happens is beyond Kandinsky’s explanation but extremely relevant to his work. To help further critique Kandinsky’s project I will rely on the work of Gilles Deleuze, in particular his book The Fold: Liebniz and the Baroque.

Before we get to introducing the intricacies of Deleuze’s work, let us ground Kandinsky’s system a little further in order to better understand how Deleuze can address Kandinsky. Kandinsky begins his second book Point and Line to Plane by noting a dual nature of the world: the external and the internal. He uses the traditional metaphor of painting as a window, except that he cites the window as a limitation. Only when “we open the door, step out of the seclusion and plunge into the outside reality [do] we become an active part of this reality and experience its pulsation with all our senses” (17). Although (or because) he is an abstract artist, Kandinsky claims that art is to “mirror itself upon the surface of our consciousness” which is not that of the material world but the spiritual. How this is achieved is unclear, although Kandinsky does claim that it takes a more developed man to experience these “psychic effects” (CSA 24). Perhaps because we are all so disenchanted with a world full of objects we see over and over, Kandinsky insists that it is only through new impressions that we can get at that psychic effect, hence the abstract nature of his art. Yet doesn’t Kandinsky in PLP insist that the formal elements of art remains the same throughout all art forms?

In Point and Line to Plane, Kandinsky meticulously examines three elements as an extension of one another across different artistic mediums: dance, architecture, music to name a few. Perhaps because Kandinsky is a painter, he explains each of these elements in terms of a visual geometry, a geometry that permeates his work. The two paintings I have selected are examples of how Kandinsky explores space. Different than Klee or Ernst, Kandinsky insists on the primacy of geometric shapes and full colors. He does not do the painterly thing and fizzle out his forms, rather his lines are sharp and his colors are well defined. This does not mean that these compositional elements are primary. Throughout his book, he uses notions like “absolute sound” (70), relative temperatures like “cold” and “warm” (59) and relative movement like “sliding” (63) to explain his compositional elements. Although these are not necessarily visual terms, they only supplement Kandinsky’s explanations. The visual components always form the basis for how we understand what is expressed in art. The dancer’s expression is inherent in the lines his body makes (42). A Chinese pagoda expresses itself “with means of equal clarity as curves leading to the point – in short precise beats audible as a transition of dissolution in which the space form fades away into the atmosphere surrounding the building” (40). Even music has lines and points that structure its expression as Kandinsky notes from a score of the motif in Beethoven’s Symphony No 5. Yet these are only cursory examples because Kandinsky is concerned with how points and lines create planes which are another way of expressing tension.

Tension is the key to Kandinsky’s theory. How we get to form tension relies on the basic building blocks of point and line. Through those formal elements, as well as the use of color, certain psychic effects build and release a certain quality. For example, in “White Line” Kandinsky characterizes a white line as tension or tension as a white line. It removes itself from the background of colors and shapes which comment on it. Furthermore, its shape seems to rise from the lower right into the upper right, to become looser. Using Kandinsky’s own examination of a similar line as an analogy, Kandinsky writes

A free curved line, [. . .] has an obstinate “look” because of its broad upper part [. . .]. This line expands as it moves upward, the expression of curvature becomes more and more forceful until the “obstinacy” attains its maximum (PSP 134).

This line has a looser feel to it’s left side and a tighter resistance on the right. This tension is inherent not only in the line as a comment to itself (from topside to bottom) but also through the various colors that it overcodes. These separate lines and colors remark on the white line through their different rhythms and repetitions. It are these rhythms and repetitions of lines that Kandinsky calls composition, the creation of qualities and quantities that interplay in tension. Tension however, is only one kind of term, the other is universal harmony. Kandinsky writes

The universal harmony of a composition can, therefore, consist of a number of complexes rising to the highest point of contrast. These contrasts can even be of an inharmonious character, and still their proper use will not have a negative effect on the total harmony but, rather, a position one, and will raise the work of art to a thing of the greatest harmony (original bold 97).

Although Deleuze and Kandinsky diverge in their understandings of art, it is in harmony and composition where they mostly agree. The differences in lines that run throughout a painting are harmonious; that is the aim of painting. Although Kandinsky here most obviously portrays it in pieces like “White Line”, where “The simplest case is the exact repetition of a straight line at equal intervals – the primitive rhythm” (original bold 95), Deleuze would disagree. There is nothing simple about even parallel straight lines. Rather such repetition is only a repetition found inherent to a series. This is the additive nature of harmonies which do “not relate multiplicity to some kind of unity, but to ‘a certain unity’ that has to offer distinctive or pertinent traits” (128). In other words, each series of lines has its own inner characteristics. This is the same kind of realization that realizes a harmony out of even divergent lines, or even lines that do not relate in the kind of “primitive rhythm” of Kandinsky. Deleuze notes that this kind of harmony passes through different kinds of strata,

preparing and resolving dissonance. [. . .] The preparation of dissonance means integrating the half-pains that have been accompanying pleasure, in such ways, that the next pain still not occur “contrary to expectations”. Thus the dog was musical when it knew how to integrate the almost imperceptible approach of the enemy, the faint hostile odor and the silent raising of the stick just prior to receiving the blow (131).

This pleasure however, is not the same as tension, it is only a unitive affect, the play of the focal point of the eye from one position to another along two convergent series which have an additive harmony on one another. In this case, the tip-toeing of the attacker, the raising of the cane and the bash is one series. The other is the series of the dog going to eat its food, eating its food and then being hit. This is like the two series of the three black triangles of “White Line” pointing through (behind) the white line. Another kind of series would be the kind of dissonance of the lower and upper left corners and the lower and upper right corners that converge without any direct touch. Rather these corners affect each other. Further understood would be to extend Liebniz’s theory of evil in which damned souls

produce a dissonance on a unique note, a breath of vengeance or resentment, a hate of God that goes to infinity; but it is still a form of music, a chord – though diabolical – since the damned draw pleasure from their pain, and especially make possible the infinite progression of perfect accords in other souls (132).

Harmony is always harmony of the inside where different essences relate in relation extending beyond each of the parts. This is how harmony is not to be found in one piece or the other but in the whole that is its own part. We can understand this as two choir members who sing in harmony together but who do not hear each other and do not know what the other is doing. Deleuze talks about these kind of series as additive effects, parts to a whole that is different from its parts, like the music of the Baroque in which many horizontal melodies converge and diverge:

It is at once the horizontal melody that endlessly develops all of its lines in extension, and the vertical harmony that establishes the inner spiritual unity or the summit, but it is impossible to know where one ends and the other begins. But, precisely, Baroque music is what can extract harmony from melody, and can always restore the higher unity toward which the arts are moving as many melodic lines: this very same elevation of harmony makes up the most general definition of what can be called Baroque music (128).

This is where the notion of composition occurs, the knowing interplay between harmonies, or tensions. This is also the apex of Deleuze’s book. In The Fold, Deleuze ends his discussion about folds on a chapter titled “The New Harmony”, exactly where Kandinsky is in the middle of his book on PLP.

Here, at the level of the composition, Kandinsky might as well end his work, but instead he goes on to further develop the idea of tension in what he calls the base plane. This last section of PLP is not a true development of the previous ideas, but more of an application in painting, although I am sure Kandinsky does not see it that way. True, Kandinsky has not explained all he knows yet but he has defined what composition is: the play of harmonies and “complexs rising to the highest point of contrast” (97). Yet what is contrasted and how harmonies rise is only explicated in Deleuze, not by Kandinsky, despite Kandinsky’s claim that his work is analytical. Further, only in the beginning of his last chapter on BP, “basic plane”, does he show how tension can develops without explaining how. We will speak at length in the near future about why different tensions happen but for now, Kandinsky’s point is more pressing as it reveals the limitations of his theory. In his viewing of two kinds of rising lines, one that goes left and one that goes right (“White Line” is one that goes right) he reveals his understanding of tension and spirituality. The harmony that

Tie[s] in with these two [contrasting] sides is another special feeling which can be explained by the characteristics already described. This feeling has a “literary” aftertaste, which again discloses the very deep-going relationships between the different expressions of art – and which, furthermore, gives us an inkling of the very deep-lying universal roots of all art forms – and, finally, of all spiritual fields. This feeling is the result of the two sole possibilities of movement of the human being, which, in spite of various combinations, actually remain only two (121).

These two feelings are of “movement into the distance” for lines moving left and for the right, “movement toward home” (121). The differentials of these two lines play against the BP of the canvas. This is to say that Kandinsky always bases the larger tensions of composition as an effect harmonizing the canvas as the BP, the square that presents the entire harmony, that even forces harmony between series that might otherwise have their own harmonies. Although Kandinsky is satisfied in his theory with this maneuver, in his painting he is not. Witness the twisting of the BP in “White Line” as the four corners are realigned with dynamic triangles that re-angle the focal point of the central space. This is an added layer of complexity for what was a simple white arc no longer arcs through the familiar square space of the BP. Although Kandinsky stops with the BP in his theory – as he wants to remain general – we see the limits of the BP. For what if there are other planes? How can spirituality be a consequence of the ever-present materiality of painting? We see then, that Kandinsky would have done well to go on, because if the BP is the final grounding of tension in painting, what if the canvas was no longer rectangular? With this simple change in material, already Kandinsky looses a full third of his theorization.

In order to re-cover what Kandinsky was interested in, we must understand the way in which he addresses the tradition he addresses. Kandinsky was very much aware of the traditional bounds of painting inherited from the Renaissance, i.e., that painting should be a window to the external world. His contemporaries too reacted to this level of materiality in all kinds of different ways. Magritte for instance, made paintings of easels completing landscapes, as well as windows which were broken (on the broken shards of glass would be a same image of the outside as the window). Kandinsky however, sought not to comment on tradition but to escape materiality through abstraction. As noted in the quote above, Kandinsky was fully aware of the window metaphor. He sought to circumvent it by “stepping outside”, but not to the material world, but the spiritual one. His play of shapes, lines and colors were meant to be a direct link to this spiritual outside, to express. As noted in his first work which is a combination of artistic statement and an analysis of color, Kandinsky defines what he means by the spiritual in art.

In Concerning the Spiritual in Art, Kandinsky presents us with a dichotomy that means to speak beyond painting and art. He posits two polar modes which are incompatible but coexisting: the material and the spiritual. These are different levels, areas where art can achieve goals. For Kandinsky most art deals with material: the drawing of objects, exposition of technique and reproduction of material. For most artists, says Kandinsky, what remains largely untapped is the spiritual in art. Only in this spiritual space, created by the artist, can an inner soul be expressed. This spirit is “‘what’ the inner truth which only art can divine, which only art can express by those means of expression which are hers alone” (9). This early aesthetic statement reflects Kandinsky’s own ambitions in his paintings. He wants to achieve a spiritual dimension of expression in his art. For this, he chooses to leave material expression completely behind. Kandinsky cites the familiarity of the world, of colors and objects to be disenchanting. Without the nominal content of traditional painting, he is freer to develop. A loose assumption Kandinsky exercises here: a man must develop with the art otherwise he will not be sensitive to its psychological effects. How these effects are mined are found for Kandinsky in his division of painting into two different elements: form and color. Although form and color are the two modes of composition through which painting expresses these two modes interact but occupy different axises. They comment on each other, and add to a sum greater than the parts but do not directly interact. Only in his second book, which we have already explored at some length, does he attempt to describe how it is form too, leads to the spiritual.

In his desire to break free of the traditional mores of painting, Kandinsky does miss a crucial point. He does not radically break with the classical viewing apparatus but modifies it by keeping the subject that is implicated by the view. After all if Kandinsky abandons every-day objects to gain an immediacy of spirituality in his painting, then why should it take a more sensitive, developed subject to view the painting, in order to understand it properly? What happened to immediacy? Should not the spiritual be apparent to the viewer, to the viewing eye without support from an apparatus? What Kandinsky wants is ambitious; an immersal of the subject into the spiritual of painting, but what he needs before this can happen is the subject to bring a certain viewing-apparatus to the painting. The viewing subject must be schooled first, in a certain kind of viewing! This too is the case with classical painting which has always been both representational and perspectivist. In a sense, Kandinsky rebukes the content of painting but preserves the form. He still is very traditional in that he is still a representationalist. Although he reacts against material representation, he replaces the object of representation with another object, the material with an abstract geometry of lines and shades, shapes and colors. In his book about Francis Bacon titled The Logic of Sensation, Deleuze comments on representation as being grounded by a kind of view:

Greek art [. . .] distinguished planes, invented a perspective and put into play light and shadow, hollows and reliefs. If we can speak of a classical representation, it is because it implies the conquest of an optical space, a distant viewing that is never frontal: the form and the ground are no longer on the same plane, the planes are distinguished from each other, and a perspective traverses them in depth, uniting the background-plane to the foreground-plane; objects overlap each other, light and shadow fill up space and make it rhythmic, the contour ceases to be the common limit on a single plane and becomes the self-limitation of the form or the primacy of the foreground. Classical representation thus takes the accident as its object, but it incorporates the accident into an optical organization that makes it something well founded (a phenomenon or a “manifestation” of essence (original italics 101).

This view, seen by the subject, grounds both the organizational lines of perspective, the event horizon of infinitude and the presence of objects whose relationship is only dynamic along a dimension of perceived depth. In paintings such as this, a whole world view (and view of the world) is accorded by which things come to be represented. What’s philosophical about such paintings can be articulated with first Descartes and then Kant. Both philosophers relegate the external world beyond immediacy, positing substance untouchable. What could only be apprehended were attributes as attributes were posited as the most direct experience we could have of a world as external. For Descartes, a “substance is a ‘thing in which what we conceive exists formally or eminently’” (Fold original italics 54). Kant takes this further when he grounds space and time as a priori, a an experiential structure inherent within all subjects. This is the bind common to traditional painting and early modern philosophy where subject and view are as one. We could not be a subject without viewing the painting through this perspective and this painting could not be as a representation without a viewing subject. Thus, paintings ground their representations and in doing so ground their viewing subjects as the subject qua focal point implicated just afore the painting at the level of the viewer’s eye. For representationalism there is no other experience of paintings. Implicit in this is traditional painting’s experiential objects. Within the objectified space of the painting objects can arise only through the specificity of attribute. Because of this, technique and cliché became the marks of good painters. Although Kandinsky reacts to this proliferation of technique and cliché vehemently, he too follows this tradition by grounding his representations on a plane. This is a different plane however, as this BP is a dimension of space not grounded on a dynamic illusion of a third dimension but on borders of the actual canvas. We can see this in the chapter on the BP. Consistently, Kandinsky formulates shapes and lines on the BP, noting that these shapes and lines have added weight depending on which quadrant of the BP is painted. Kandinsky is aware of the BP’s affects but considers this to be the mode of painting. For instance, in the examination of two reflected lines, he writes

Turning this example upside-down is especially fitted to the investigation of the effects of “above” and “below” and this is something the reader can do for himself. The “content” of the line changes so radically that the line is no longer recognizable: the obstinacy disappears completely and is replaced by a laborious tension (PLP 135).

Further, he examines the affects of the base plane, various times, diving the BP into “four primary parts, each of which has its specific appearance” (126). Never mind that these corners of the BP are differentiated only in position to the viewer. Of course, this is the case when paintings can be hung in all kinds of ways different from how the artist painted it. Nonetheless, even before any markings are made, Kandinsky is describing an apparatus that pre-organizes the work. For instance, these corners touch at what Kandinsky calls “the ‘indifferent’ center, out which tensions flow diagonally” (126). This is very much like the lines of perspective that flow out from the viewing subject of more traditional material representation. How has Kandinsky modified the classical view of perspective? It is as if the subject were released from his position on the ground and thrown into the air to see the world as a bird’s eye system of Cartesian coordinates. This view is still consistent with classical perspectives, because it assumes an objective gaze that is all the more objective because even further, the subjective field of view is presented without a mediating subject. Now, the viewing subject sees as a God, all the field for there would be nothing left from his sight. All that remains is the null point of a zero center. You can see then, how this new viewing apparatus of the subject is modified but simultaneously retains the basic system of representation. One suggests that this field of representation is all the more deceptive because its viewing apparatus is entrenched, made invisible. This is not to say that spiritual immediacy should be founded on a materiality that is not canvas or rectangular or planar. Rather, if there is a spirituality of the art work, let it be of the art work itself, and not the added effect of the viewing eye. In a sense, we must approach the works as naïve and let the work tells us of what it will without pre-focusing the work in any particular way. As Kandinsky writes

Our materialistic age has produced a type of spectator or “connoisseur,” who is not content to put himself opposite a picture and let it say its own message. Instead of allowing the inner value of the picture to work, he worries himself in looking for “closeness to nature,” or “temperament,” or “handling,” or outer expression to arrive at the inner meaning (49).

It is exactly this inner value that is locked away when art must always be formulated off a theoritical, pre-fabricated BP. In the context of the BP’s tensions, this inner value remains a kind of surplus, the originary excess that all works of art retain, even though this value can be obscured by inner tensions. As mentioned previously, we can see Kandinsky’s own attempt at shaving away the BP in “White Line” which when combined with the pluralistic, multifaceted background, obscures the effect of the BP on the “White Line”. In effect, he paints with more sophistication than he is aware.

If abstract art is not enough, what else is needed to get at this spirituality? Is not harmony enough? Indeed, with Deleuze we see that harmony is enough, although there are two consequences of a radical harmony: 1) The viewing subject as apparatus, not as actual person, must be gotten rid of and 2) we must understand what it is that is harmonized. If harmony is a sum that is greater than its parts, then what are the parts? Are these parts sums in themselves or are they only parts, partial and incomplete without the harmony? We shall see in a moment that these two questions are related and that the answer to the second naturally follows from the answer to the first.

Too often are we used to treating all matters that we culturally hold equivalent in the same manner, oblivious to the individual differences which determine preferential treatment. To see all paintings in the same way would be to confuse an actual, real painting with our shared cultural assumptions of what paintings are and how they function. In effect, we would confuse the objects we place for the cultural place where we shelve objects. To this end, the removal of the subject’s viewing lense leaves a void that needs to be addressed. Certainly many paintings ask to be treated in the same way. They request that we read this one like the last one, and thus are painted as such. This not need be the case however, with abstract art, or with art that is painted with the avant garde in mind. With this, we almost have to forget who painted what, to see what the painting itself expresses as its own essence. This is the understanding of philosophies of difference, of which Deleuze is par excellence. This means that every difference is itself an identity, and that identity is not to be found on the negative transcendental qualities of X is not-Y, not-Z, not-A and not-B but that X is its own difference as an affirmation of X. Taken in this way, it is as if Deleuze would take the viewing lense of the transcendental subject (who sees the field from above as if a God) and smash this lense against the viewing field. Space then becomes deterritorialized as topographical differences arise on their own originary tension. Kandinsky is here at this point of originary difference in the beginning of PLP in his chapter on points.

On his examination of points Kandinsky attempts to describe an isolated phenomenon before building up to the next step. In this isolation, Kandinsky is at his most purest but what he misses when he goes to the next step is to extend this prior understanding to the next level. He discards what he has learned in order to embrace what he knows. Kandinsky begins by writing that these points are both “an incorporeal thing” (25) and a “Disturbance originating from within” (26), both of which he explains by saying that points are “‘human’ in nature” (25). These meanings are conceptual but they betray Kandinsky’s first grasp of difference. But this is different from the alienated substance of Descartes, rather as Kandinsky explains early on one must have a direct apprehension.

In a conversation with an interesting person, we endeavor to get at his fundamental ideas and feelings. We do not bother about the words he uses, nor the spelling of those words, nor the breath necessary for speaking them, nor the movements of his tongue and lips, nor the psychological workings on our brain, nor the physical sound in our ear, nor the physiological effect on our nerves. We realize that these things, though interesting and important, are not the main things of the moment, but that the meaning and idea is what concerns us. We should have the same feeling [read attitude] when confronted with a work of art. When this becomes general the artist will be able to dispense with natural form and colour and speak in a purely artistic language (CSA 49).

Interesting to note is that Kandinsky follows this exegesis of what not to do after complaining about the cultivated spectator who brings his cultural baggage to the scene of art. Kandinsky does not see cultural baggage as innately different from a mechanistic analysis because the two are the same for him. Of course, we might be interested with how paintings are deployed in various cultural settings and views, but that is an examination of culture. On the contrary, a direct apprehension to the level of the interesting person’s ideas require that we pay intimate attention to what he says and how he uses those aforementioned lips, tongues and sounds without being preoccupied with the mechanics of them. We must rather, pass through these various enunciations and grasp at the wholeness of his speech and his gestures in order to reach a level by which parts are of a whole and that ideas and meaning are immanent a present expression.

Language is perhaps a bad example because of its loaded nature. Deleuze presents us with an understanding of the point which he borrows from Liebniz that extends Kandinsky’s point about points. Liebniz is famous for his contribution to mathematics (he founded calculus at the same time Newton did) as well as his philosophical monadology. Curiously enough, this philosophy addressed Descartes’ dualism and it is this dualism in painting which we shall remove. Aforementioned, Descartes separated the subject from the world by claiming that originary substance is different from attribute, that substance was a conceptual matter of necessity but only through the accidental encounters on the level of attribute. As Deleuze writes, “for Descartes, the essential attribute is confused with substance, to the point that individuals now tend only to be modes of the attribute as it generally is” (54). Only through an understanding of attribute qua substance qua expression can we return individuality and distinctness to its rightful place. The traditional grammatical example demands distinction between subject and attribute. The scheme of attribution works by first expressing a quality and designating an essence that is to say, the subject is the basis by which the predicate acts. However, with Liebniz we have

the event [which] is deemed worthy of being raised to the state of a concept: the Stoics accomplished this by making the event neither an attribute nor a quality, but the incorporeal predicate of a subject of the proposition (not “the tree is green,” but “the tree greens . . .”). They conclude that the proposition stated a “manner of being” of the thing [. . .] and they put manner in the place of essence (53).

It is this manner that replaces the conceptual substance in the monad. We return to Kandinsky’s characterization of the point as a “disturbance originating from within” (26). This is to say that a conceptual point is the abstraction of manner as difference. When the actual point becomes, so becomes the monad in its characteristic “as an independent being and its subordination transforms itself into an inner purposeful one” (28). Kandinsky is only right when he is at his most theoretical for he at once contemplates the point as its own being but looses this when he subordinates all points as the same point. Rather we should being to understand that each point, or monad, has its own life that does not require substance. In isolation, monads are clearly what they are, but what about in tandem?

When Kandinsky extends the point by “another force which develops not within the point, but outside of it” (54), he begins to conceive a line. But this force is not from the outside of the point but from within it. He mistakes the line as an extended force that erases the point because he thinks that points have an innate substance, but this is not so. Rather, the line is an extension of a point’s force from where arises an expression and harmony that creates the whole. This can be understood from calculus where Liebniz conceived of a rate of change different at each point of the arc of a line. Line is a series of monads each of which extend their differential force along the arc, passing the expression as line. Monads in series is the variation of a curve along a curve as the measurement of movement takes movement as measurement. A single monad then, objectively speaking, is a differential, a rate of change that expresses itself as its own variation. Deleuze writes

Moving from a branching of inflection, we distinguish a point that is no longer what runs along inflection, nor is it the point of inflection itself; it is the one in which the lines perpendicular to tangents meet in a state of variation. It is not exactly a point but a place, a position, a site, a “linear focus,” a line emanating from lines. To the degree it represents variation or inflection, it can be called point of view. Such is the basis of perspectivism, which does not mean a dependence in respect to a pregiven or defined subject; to the contrary, a subject will be what comes to the point of view, or rather what remains in the point of view. That is why the transformation of the object refers to a correlative transformation of the subject [. . .]. The point of view is not what varies with the subject [. . .] it is [. . .] the condition in which an eventual subject apprehends a variation. (original italics, 19-20).

This is how space becomes topographical, as monads express themselves in tandem. Further this is how paintings can become expressive not in space but by compressing and releasing space, by moving through the relative temperatures of “hot and cold.” The language Kandinsky uses to try and explicate colors expresses not temperature or depth, but relative variation of one degree or another. It is these many different points, intensities and lines of force that build the harmony by commenting as a whole, on it holographically. For this, each monad has with it, the whole engendered, a microcosm that is relative to its degree of variation of the macrocosm. But one should not fall back to a comfortable transcendent objectivity to find grounding for monads, rather it is the monads that comment on each other to topographize a fuzzy objective ground. A given topography does exist in two, three or four dimensions, but more correctly, expresses each dimension in tandem. Each point is a difference but together, any three points have a rhythm that convergences as the seeds for a plane, not it is not that planes have seeds for points. To further explicate, Deleuze recapitulates Liebniz’s statement about the monads and the city.

For if [. . .] Liebniz makes the monad a sort of point of view on the city, must we understand that a certain form corresponds to each point of view? In conic sections, there is no separate point of view to which the ellipse would return, and another for the parabola, and another for the circle. The point of view, the summit of the cone, is the condition under which we apprehend the group of varied forms or the series of curves to the second degree. It does not suffice to state that the point of view apprehends a perspective, a profile that would each time offer the entirety of a city in its own fashion. For it also brings forth the connection of all related profiles, the series of all curvatures or inflections. What can be apprehended from one point of view is therefore neither a determined street nor a relation that might be determined with other streets, which are constants, but the variety of all possible connections between the course of a given street and that of another. The city seems to be a labyrinth that can be ordered. The world is an infinite series of curvatures or inflections, and the entire world is enclosed in the soul from one point of view (24).

Rather then, monads here are fragments of the smashed lense where that objective viewing apparatus has fragmented into subjective, continually variable instances of its viewed objects. You might ask at this point, what determines how monads express? If a monad is a variation on a point in concert with others, might not a differential of a monad encompass other monads in tandem? And further, is this not what a line, or a plane or a tangent is? The answer is yes, this is how monads, are. According to Deleuze, monads

includes the whole series [and] conveys the entire world, but does not express it without expressing more clearly a small region of the world, a “subdivision” [. . .]. Two souls do not have the same order, but neither do they have the same sequence or the same clear or enlightened region. It might even be stated that insofar as it is filled with folds that stretch to infinity, the soul can always unfold a limited number of them inside itself, those that make up its subdivision or borough. A definition of individuation remains to be clarified: if only individuals exist, it is not because they include the series in a certain order and according to a given region; it is even the inverse that holds (original italics, 25).

Thus we have both the world within the subject but the subject too within the world. Either one could not be without the other. This is radically different from Kandinsky’s comprehension of the BP as an empty basic plane that already has differentials of tension and place. This is how the BP itself is a work of art before Kandinsky paints, but also how the BP insisted by Kandinsky can obliterate the art of an artwork by denying that artwork its own relations. In a half step, this too is how monads can be in a series or line, but how that line is also a continuous variation of monads like notes in melody. What gives a line its inner tension, as Kandinsky might say, is what makes a melodic line harmonize not to another line but to itself. This is where Deleuze comes up with the notion of the fold.

Further more, although these monad/points maybe one sided, how Deleuze comprehends these monads are as folds. Each one interlocks with their neighbor and expression dominos to infinity. A line on a painting may retain its force through all the swirling mass of colors and lines it crosses, but this line too can extend outward beyond the BP, as its own tension to comment on its surroundings. The Mona Lisa can smile at Guernica all the while both paintings retain their own intensity as if in solitude. We can see this play of commentary and folding in and out in “Several Circles No. 323”. Circles themselves for Kandinsky retained a special meaning, as an extended point, a fortissimo vibration that is its own inside. Literally, these circles are what Deleuze might call incompossible, as each wraps itself within its own world, its own highlights, its own note. They nonetheless play with one another (in what is compossible) like two songs from two different radios at the same time, neither fully aware of the other but in harmony, of the same world. Thus, only on the level of the fold that extends (despite) variation that we begin to converge on what Deleuze calls the second story of the Baroque, what Kandinsky might call the level of the spiritual.

Again, recalling Kandinsky’s polar modes of materiality and spirituality, Kandinsky notes that these two points are mutually exclusive aims of art. One can desire to capture the material or one can desire to capture the spiritual. Kandinsky professes to the spiritual, as we see in his art, but theorizes on the level of the material, basing his theory of composition on the tension inherent in the BP. Indeed, Kandinsky should aim a little higher, but such heights are difficult to metaphysically describe as each painting is in itself a monad incompossible because of its specificity, wrapped up in its own world. Again, only on a level beyond differentiation, where variation reach beyond material bounds to enfold other variations, do we find yet another higher story that achieves a purity, a reflective unity of its own. This is how life rises up from its plastic forces where

The organism is defined by its ability to fold its own parts and to unfold them, not to infinity, but to a degree of development assigned to its own species. Thus an organism is enveloped by other organisms, one within another (interlocking of germinal matter), like Russian dolls. The first fly contains the seeds of all flies to come, each being called in its turn to unfold its own parts at the right time. And when an organism dies, it does not really vanish, but folds in upon itself (8).

Further, this is how a body arises, the folding of one monad over others, consistently and each differential monad expressing its own difference through the body of many variations. This body is thus defined by a dominate monad as “a clear and distinguished zone of expression” (original italics, 98). Thus while on a lower level, we have monads of continuous variation, blind to each other like the several circles whose pink is pink and the other whose yellow is yellow, separated and happy in their separate spaces. Simultaneously on the upper level, we have the painting an entire differential, as harmonious, where melodies enfold and interplay folding and unfolding on each other like so many children passing the hot potato, some quickly, some hanging onto it, others giggling and some hiding back, but each in their proper turn. In terms of curvature, Deleuze writes of the two floors:

On the upper level we have a line of variable curvature, without coordinates, a curve with infinite inflection, where inner vectors of concavity mark for each ramification the position of individual monads in suspension. But only on the lower level have we coordinates that determine extreme, extrema that define the stability of figures [. . .]. This is the organization of the Baroque house with its division in two floors, one individual weightlessness, the other in a gravity of mass (102).

This is not to say however that there are two paintings, but rather that there are two paintings because there is one. It is impossible to tell where one floor ends and the other begins because these two comment wholly on one another. Deleuze attests to the inner beauty of fabric, the folding textures of Baroque characters whose ruffles accentuate a form by hiding it all together. Under the dress is an elegance that is common with the dress. On the one hand we

are dealing with two cities, a celestial Jerusalem and an earthy one, but with the rooftops and foundations of a same city, and two floors of a same house (119).

Although in actuality, the two floors are the same floor and the house is as one whole. This is perhaps too simple, and would repeat the dualism of Descartes, for there is not one spirituality or one materiality but a mix which is impossible to differentiate. Perception, expression and hallucination are the same for each has no object but subsists over the artwork as a second floor, simultaneously folded in and enfolded. Otherwise said, the object of perception is the perception, and the expressed essence is the attribute expressed. By extension, there are not just two Jerusalems, as that would insist on the same dualism, but a plurality. The man on the corner selling hot dogs is a different Jerusalem than the man on the other corner selling popcorn. The small dirty children who run around pick-pocketing have different Jerusalems each, and each Jerusalem is wrapped up in the differentials of the children. Likewise, the woman in the limousine, the fountain that breaks sometimes, the courier in his own car are all Jerusalem in convergence and yet each separately is divergent and enfolding. Thus, we have in the body of the mass of people many Jerusalems, and we also have the entire city as a whole, floating animated as if a cartoon coding through the dirty streets, the churches, mosques and synagogues. In this way, spirituality is inherent in all forms, in all matter, in all art. As Kandinsky claims that there is no pure decorative art, and even art meant as decoration is not lifeless (47). Thus we have the two meta-levels, spiritual and materiality as extreme points themselves, polar modes which may resist one another, one being made of porous sponge-like matter and the other made of clear airy mist, but the two are the same, commenting on one another. Where art enters as art is not on the level of the purely material, although we might begin with BP, but it is neither incorporeal, as might be a consistent feeling or a tendency. What rises through is the expression of both, a compossible world, divergent from this one perhaps, but all the more in active although not in force but in presence qua force qua presence. We can end thus, with a quote from Deleuze, as he explains that it is not the sum of the monads that realize a body. Rather it takes both floors,

the bending of the two levels, the zone of inseparability that produces the crease or seam. To state that the bodies realize is not to say that they are real: they become real with respect to what is actual in the soul (inner action or perception). Something completes or realizes the body. A body is not realized, but what is realized in the body is currently perceived in the soul. The reality of the body is the realization of phenomena in the body (120).

Spirituality is achieved as a realized shock, of the whole puzzle or of pieces that slide into place all the while the thing remains the same and is transformed or reaches another level.

Thus, contrary to Kandinsky, it is not the content of objective perspective that derails the spiritual in painting. Such content is itself the expression of materiality, but that expression is itself only a symptom of a dominate monad, a larger differential, one that would extend and overcode other monads and signify only itself over and over, everywhere. This one view demands itself objective over all, that there is only this one world, one focal point, one view, only this one transcendental acumen. In much the same way, Kant binds self and subject as in every experience through the grounding of a priori transcendental machines. This consistent view is a regurgitation that denies the larger body as constant variations, intensities that point to a many inflected theme. As art is expression, so must each art have clear expression. This means, and Kandinsky is on the right track, to replace the representation with an immediacy of access, to grasp that expression and not mistake it through something else. What he forgoes in this access however was the subject, the missing mediator. This does not suggest that everyone viewing art would view art the same way. We are all comments on each other, the artwork and the world. Each color is a comment on another color because each color is a shade of itself. A soul is a differential, which has a particular view, yet this vantage point need not dominate the artwork nor need it insist on its mastery by folding the artwork into an apparatus alien to the artwork. Thus while a body and a world exists as freedom, a zone of unfettered expression, so too an artwork must be free, on the BP, in your head, on the wall, unfettered and unchained. Art qua spirituality cannot uplift the subject unless the subject too is willing to be uplifted, brought to that seam or crease, to be enveloped, enfolded. If we want art to express, we should not fold the artwork into ourselves but be folded, unfolded and enfolded.

Deleuze, Gilles. The Fold: Liebniz and the Baroque. Trans. Tom Conley. Minneapolis: Minnesota 1993.
Kandinsky, Wassily. Concerning the Spiritual in Art. Trans. M.T.H. Sadler. New York: Dover 1977.
—. Point and Line to Plane. Trans. Howard Dearstyne and Hilla Rebay. New York: Dover 1979.

What ever happened to Deleuze?

The older I get, the more I find myself agreeing with Kant’s thoughts on things.

This is a little disappointing to me…

Dialectical Nihilism

Many of the entries I have posted on here are an attempt to try and find a rational application of ideas, or the imprint of massive theories onto the chaotic transgressions of daily life. Theories themselves when applicable to meaning, society and culture, prove effective when they

1. can justify or explain a particular situation — why things are
2. grasp the relationships of various categories as they function by highlighting a fulcrum upon which meaning is generated.

For this reason, it may be incoherent or disjointed to present a theory simply as a theory for its own sake. Such theorization is an artifice of academia and not at all pragmatic. Nonetheless, I present below a theory I batted around a bit a few years ago in order to try and make sense of what I was doing. I am not going to apply the theory here, but simply present it as a point of reference.

Forgive me, if this seems too academic.

Dialectical Nihilism

we have heard of dialectical materialism — and dialectical idealism. the former is used to describe the adoptation of hegelian dialectics by marx… an explanation of production (the formation of history through class struggle). the latter i have heard as a reflective description of hegel, when in fact dialectics itself in general is associated with hegel, although at its root we can get socratic dialogue. fine whatever, classical blahblah. but can be mix traditions? nietzsche and hegel don’t go together. but let’s try:

what about dialectical nihilism?

step 1. simple nihilism in-itself. we have the reactionary nihilist who claims “i believe in nothing”. this is coupled with what you might call evangelical atheism in which this nonbeliever poo-poos everything that is “meaningful” — claiming such people are idiots. let’s take the example of God. such a nihilist would eagerly either make fun of or try and convince believers that there is nothing instead of God.

incidentially this form of nihilism is what i associate with self proclaimed atheists and nihilists, which is why i do not take up such a title. it’s an obscene sort of behavior which is hypocritical.

step 2. negative nihilism. most atheists do not reach this point, or atleast if they do they are quiet about it. this is where nihilism recognizes that while “i believe in nothing” this has a negative bearing in extension. such a nihilist would see believers of God and say, “well good for them. at least they are happy… i guess”.

step 3. nihilism for-itself. such a nihilist can go to church because of the pleasure of other people’s feelings. of the beautiful architecture, of the pleasantness of the hymns and the freshness of goodwill — and enjoy the simulacra of religion and not see any contradiction because while there may be nothing, what does it matter what others believe in? let’s enjoy this nothing in its nothinghood. perhaps sartre…? most people will never reach this level ethics in their life, this adherence to a productive principle.

step 4. this is where nihilism itself is a notion. what to call it? if this was truly hegelian it would be the reversal or what sartre might say as nihilism in-itself-for-itself; but such a mode is often found in either the 2nd or 3rd step, not the 4th. here a nihilist can claim that “there is nothing for me to grasp; why shouldn’t i believe in whatever? at least i am happy… i guess”. what makes this the 4th step is in the empty form of the notion — which of course in hegel’s 4th is like this 4th — a divorce of content from the empty pure form (reality). in this example it is expressed as a separation of belief from reality… a point at which some christians i have met have attained.

at its core, we have a resemblance of nietzsche… in the form of hegel. not to say that nietzsche is synonymous with nihilism. certainly nihilism is a simplified form. what might make this nietzschiean is in how we divorce a position’s normal “expected” valiance from its expression… not just that we deal with nihilism and therefore must deal with the origins of values. we have a movement into the origins of the seed of belief in that 4th nihilist claim…

so but basically this can be understood as a justification of christianity or whatever through nihilism.