« Posts under Theory

Against Method: Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge

Against Method: Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge Against Method: Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge by Paul Karl Feyerabend
My rating: 5 of 5 stars

Feyerabend writes a difficult book here, but one which is necessary. Taking a radically different perspective on the aesthetics of what theory is, Feyerabend attack one of the scared cows of science and mathematics — that of consistency.

In some ways, Feyerabend could have raised objections more metaphysically — that ideas have at their germination roots outside of a given domain — that culture plays a role in utilizing domains in one area to influence another — that science is a socially generated practice, on that mistakes methodology for reality — but in other ways, Feyerabend does well by sticking very close to his topic. His use of Galileo as an example is of interest, since he returns to it often but it is in his later chapters that his critique really stands out.

Basically Feyerabend shows us that knowledge is always procedural. Knowledge and theory are generated through processes of agency. By attempting to manipulate or influence a specific phenomenon, we generate procedures to gain access to that phenomenon. This requires that we calibrate our actions to an appropriate cut. Nonetheless, any cut we calibrate to is simultaneously a distortion of the very object of study, because it casts it in a certain relationship. Thus

Expressing it differently, we may say that the assumption of a single coherent world-view that underlies all of science is either a metaphysical hypothesis trying to anticipate a future unity, or a pedagogical fake; or it is an attempt to show, by a judicious up-and downgrading of disciplines, that a synthesis has already been achieved. This is how fans of uniformity proceeded in the past (cf. Plato’s lists of subjects in Chapter vii of his Republic), these are the ways that are still being used today. A more realistic account, however, would be that ‘[t]here is no simple “scientific” map of reality–or if there were, it would be much too complicated and unwieldy to be grasped or used by anyone. But there are many different maps of reality, from a variety of scientific viewpoints’

One should be quick to realize that Feyerabend is not against science at all; in fact he encourages it in his “irresponible” and “anarchist” ways. What Feyerabend is objecting to is the imagined consistency/consensus of science, a “sacred cow” of science all the more because science doesn’t need such a “petit object a” in order to function. One of the underlying criticisms that Feyerabend levels is that all social institutions (including science) are in fact first and foremost, social institutions. We understand this to be even more true when we realize that the academic/scientific community often operates as a ranking system more than as a theory generating procedure; that grants and individuals are awarded more for position than they are for work. That the entire procedure of science is one of self promotion (through the modality of whatever science they are using) more than anything else.

In some ways, Feyerabend does well to criticize past methods in order to highlight inconsistencies in how they are aestheticized and presented. But this of course, will stop no one, because past procedures are in the past. After all, aren’t we better now?

I cannot stop praising his book, because there is so much in here. I appreciate the clarity and freshness with which Feyeraband approaches this topic. On a more abstract level, one that I think Feyerabend would appreciate, is that we should approach all polemics and theories understanding that they are generated through the auspices of their own consistency and meaning. We often reject theories and ideas just like we reject people — they either don’t make the cut due to some personal inclination, or they are competitors for the same social capital. Often, these are the same thing. I whole heartedly agree with Feyerabend. With the lack of any “true” authority, one that “naturally” supersedes whatever authority we could imagine here on Earth (as there is none like that), we ought to utilize any theory that allows us to increase our agency. Should we not desire any particular agency, we should embrace any idea for what it is worth, at the time that we need it. Of course, some ideas will become undecideable should the foundation for that idea be incommensurable with our own foundation. But that is not a fault of that idea. This is merely the fault of our own localization. Sometimes, a question simply isn’t available from a given point of view because its context is not available.

This is of course, in a big way, where Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason steps in, and it is at this point that Feyerabend stops short. He doesn’t wish to get into the logistics of what is reasonable. He only wishes that we set ourselves free of the chains by which we adhere to an image of what good science ought to look like so that we can do better science. And for that, I find that there is a resonance with martial arts, or with music or any other technicality/agency. We must learn the basics to define what the modality is. From that point on, mastery begins when we start to release ourselves from technique in order to be more appropriate to whatever situation we find ourselves in, simply because technique is a pedagogical tool, and its rigid organization will make certain acts impossible because they are incommensurable with that technique.

Ultimately, consistency is how we make sense of a localization for the purposes of ordinance (organization). We must never mistake the map for the territory since the territory is always changing as our desires/designs and agential relations change — so we too change.

View all my reviews

The Paradox of Subjectivity: The Self in the Transcendental Tradition

The Paradox of Subjectivity: The Self in the Transcendental TraditionThe Paradox of Subjectivity: The Self in the Transcendental Tradition by David Carr
My rating: 5 of 5 stars

Carr presents us with an interesting puzzle, that speaks about the role of self in the transcendental tradition. In some sense, it’s not a puzzle at all. Kantian scholars often look to the point of “subjectivity” as central to Kant’s critique in inquiry. This is not so. If you read Critique of Pure Reason closely, you will see that Kants main critique is about reason itself; the way in which reason works to supplement understanding, often extending understanding beyond the bounds of what is “reasonable” for reason to speculate on.

Carr shows us at first, the bumbling that rises from the transcendental tradition. He starts off with Heidegger in order to critique him, going through Husserl and then ending later on with Kant. About halfway through we get a glimpse that the two “selves” empirical and transcendental have in fact no bearing within the tradition as a kind of truth. Rather these two points are bracketed speculations. Towards the end then, Carr, goes against the tradition of scholars that wish to push Husserl and Kant into “metaphysical” speculation, tentatively stating that

Both philosophers recognized, I think, that their transcendental procedure did not authorize the transition to metaphysical claims

And this is so! The paradox is rightly present because the scholars that follow misread and wished to pursue their own agenda of subjectivity. In this sense, this already short book, could be even shorter, as the paradox lies wholly within trying to make a round hole squared. For what Carr sets out to do, he does it quite well. Not an easy book to read, because of its heavy terminology, but it is in fact still an introductory book, although it serves as an introduction to a very complex topic.

View all my reviews

Time and Free Will: An Essay on the Immediate Data of Consciousness

Time and Free Will: An Essay on the Immediate Data of ConsciousnessTime and Free Will: An Essay on the Immediate Data of Consciousness by Henri Bergson
My rating: 4 of 5 stars

Once again, Bergson takes us in another direction. He excels at pulling out the underlying relations that structure methodology. He exposes how we construct regular notions such as time, space, self and so on — showing us that such terms are actually heterogeneous. That we assume that the formality of language and conception is what things are; ignoring the uncertainty and difference that characterizes how we consider ourselves in a constant becoming all of our own.

At the heart of this essay, Bergson takes us towards free will, understanding that our conception of selfhood as a social manifestation (so we live outside ourselves) or as an “external projection of the other” which is reached by “deep introspection” but not given to “states” that are “amenable to measure”. This suspension of our sense of being between these two regimes disallows us our freedom since we are rarely grasping ourselves and instead dealing with how we are meant to consider ourselves. This is akin to unraveling how we know ourselves; we consider who we are by slowly replacing ourselves with our own map of ourselves, and then forgetting that the map is a map, and considering the map as who we are. This insightful proposition sounds oddly postmodern but it originates for Bergson as the understanding that we are not a static field of temporal absolutes. Rather, we are a process of integration — non-repeatable and consistently in flux. It is Bergson’s criticism of philosophy and science that we ought to know ourselves by the invariance that we come to misrecognize what we are as we always eliminating contingency and difference only to assuming the inadequacy of our ideas as being static and non-changing despite the inconsistency of our lived experience… as we use our social identity (as an unchangeable reference) to anchor our physical invariance. This is also why Bergson finds fault with causality; because all points on the manifold are localizations. Extensions of localizations will never attain stability with identity.

This amounts to saying that the more we strengthen the principle of causality, the more we emphasize the difference between a physical series and a psychical one.

It is for this reason; this difference between our psychical inconsistency that is immeasurable and our “physical series” anchored in social identity that we find ourselves with free will. In essence, because we are constantly becoming- through our own sense of process and not one that is grounded on the mechanized clocks of human coordination. Bergson questions social time as being time; instead he seeks to highlight how we generate ourselves and constantly make ourselves through the immediacy of our lived contexts. Confusing this with our ordered institutions and our prized laws of equivalence and mathematical measurement would be to further alienate who we are by mistaking our tools for what we really are.

I have read quite a few of Bergson’s books by this point. I had no idea this was his doctoral thesis until I was nearly done with the book. (I tend not to read covers or jackets). In this we see the promise of Bergson’s originality; his ability to suss out difference in approach and concentrate on how the acceptance of formal invariance in method creates a context by which centralized content often doesn’t match centralized content. In many ways, this is why different disciplines cannot speak to one another; because they assume too much and do not recognize their own assumptive principles. Because, to question such principles would be, often, to destroy the very discipline those methods generate. In this, Bergson is refreshing!

View all my reviews

The Social Conquest of Earth

The Social Conquest of EarthThe Social Conquest of Earth by Edward O. Wilson
My rating: 3 of 5 stars

In this well written book, biologist Edward O Wilson would recalibrate our sense of being from individualists to a group. He notes that the balance of being human is a constant tension, one that suspends us between being too individualistic (like lone predators) and too group oriented (like ants, which are basically one individual in many bodies). He traces the development of humans as coarising with language and social development so that at a more abstract level, it’s not consciousness that develops but rather social being which develops of which consciousness is but a very localized piece.

I am not certain that Wilson gets across his aesthetic clearly. I think that if he were to speak more openly about what he is drawing, people would be off put. But by trying to maintain one foot in science, and the other in terms of the social complexity he would compare us to (ants, bees, lions), he comes fairly close. Part of our problem in understanding this eusocial view of humankind lies in how we often consider ourselves a competitors. In capitalism there is little room for community; or rather, what community does exist exists at an unconscious level. WE do the community without thinking. We follow each other, parrot each other’s gestures and copy one another linguistically, vocally, and physically as a matter of calibration.

In a way, this book reminds me of the work of the speculative work of Julian Jaynes Origin-Consciousness-Breakdown-Bicameral-Mind, although Jaynes was far more aggressive and wide reaching in his exploration of the concept than Wilson. Wilson’s main emphasis however isn’t on the science, although he is careful to always cite science at every turn. What Wilson is more after is a high level abstract vision of how to organically consider what humans are, what we do and where we would go.

I think his emphasis on Paul Gauguin is meant to emphasis this inquiry, although it gets a little lost in the light citations and various explorations in science. Obviously this is not a scientific part; the citations are not overboard. But Wilson is trying to show us that he’s not running on crazy here either. It’s a difficult balance to strike, and I am not sure that Wilson does as compelling a job as he means to. Still, this book is an interesting look at an old question, and not all that difficult to read. Worth taking a look, if the topic interests you.

View all my reviews

I am a strange loop

I Am a Strange LoopI Am a Strange Loop by Douglas R. Hofstadter
My rating: 2 of 5 stars

In I am a strange loop Douglas Hofstader asks the question, who am “I”; what is the self?

Consistent with his position as a non-jargonist, Hofstader refuses to accept domain limits on his question. Thus, Hofstader ends up at an impasse with the terms he uses (self, substance, pattern) as these terms “pull in” the domain limits that he refuses to recognize. Rather than allowing his inquiry to asymptotically approach a correct calibration to highlight the cut that outlines selfhood, (which would require that he float his terms into a new mapping), instead Hofstader insists on the reality of his non-jargon words and implicitly runs us into a kind of Kantian paradox in which on the one hand, we have an “I” of personal experience and on the other, we have only the endless repetition of patterns..

By insisting on a lack of limit in his questioning and forcing the terms he wants to apply to every context of inquiry, ironically, Hofstader’s method recreates the very answer he finds ridiculous: “Soul regression”, i.e., “inside me there is a little man who runs me; inside him there is a little man who runs him… ad infinitum”. By insisting on finding a narcissistic trace of selfhood at each level, his inquiry would have us, at every level, produce a trace of self from each domain to its sub-domain and so on.

Is this not an example of how an inquiry through its formal presentation reproduces the structure of the answer they seek? Hofstader rejects the ridiculous implications of soul regression yet he seems willing to only accept an answer that would structurally be its equivalent.

His discard of jargon in an attempt to be more “real” (good ole American pragmatism) ignores the primary fact that not-all queries can be sensible in only some domains. Looking for the self in physics is narcissistic. It’s like looking for ingredients that make a good breakfast in building code. Incidentally, this reminds me of how Kantian scholars look to critique of pure reason as a book about subjectivity, ignoring the fact that Kant’s main focus is about “pure” reason alone. Subjectivity is just another example of a transcendental chimera. Yet, I digress…

Overall, Hofstader’s book is interesting, and well written, as he explains complex ideas without the use of very technical terms. There is another way to debunk Hofstader’s reasoning however, and that’s to note what he takes for granted conceptually and what he questions. It’s of interesting to note that in many examples, Hofstader replaces nonsense terms for the very objects he questions. When questioning the veracity of mental phenomenon, he does this often. His move is to show that a lack of difference (physically) is no difference. This is silly ludicrous as he is basically transposing one term with a specific context into another domain and then demonstrating through the equivalence of nonsense terms that this object doesn’t hook into anything. This makes Hofstader a bad philosophy though, because in essence he is begging the question.

I think the main critique of this book is that if there is ever a point at which we need jargon, it’s to recognize the complex agency of those fields. Jargon words exist to express relationships that are otherwise difficult to apprehend without those jargonistic contexts. Yes, an unfortunate side effect of jargon is elitism, but that’s often the case with people who want to differentiate themselves for the purposes of status through any means necessary, so we will always have elitism, even without jargon. By removing the jargon and consideration of other kinds of logics, Hofstader limits his inquiry to a single domain, one which he recognizes as being overwhelmingly valid. This creates the same problem as mentioned before: he is looking for an answer in the wrong area. It’s like someone insisting that we find a definition for “life” in terms of building code, or trying to find a hadron in terms of biology — and upon not finding this concept expressible in the domain of their choice, concluding that this concept must be bunk all along.

I am not stating that another domain has the answer, or even a coherent answer. I am simply stating that Hofstader ties his own hands together and then through a series of very clever but limited inquiries begs the question over and over to conclude that the self does not really exist because he can’t find it present in all domains equally. What a narcissistic endeavor he has undertaken.

View all my reviews

What Is Philosophy?

What Is Philosophy?What Is Philosophy? by Gilles Deleuze
My rating: 4 of 5 stars

I read this book three times over 10 years, before I really began to appreciate it. In a way, A Thousand Plateau‘s success kind of blinded people to what Deleuze and Guattari were doing. So this next book, feels more like a snap back. It’s not the poetry approach, it’s not the postmodernism. Here’s an analytic account of concepts. What makes a concept? How does it work?

What is Philosophy comes close to approximating the relationship between domains and logic. But there is still a tendency here to wax about relationships rather than to cut to an essential conciseness. Although they hit on many conceptual relationships I agree with their essential categorization of concepts (philosophy, science and art) reads too much like a list. To understand conceptualization as confronting chaos is correct. But the event that undergrids Deleuze’s conception of a mark on chaos, a primary cut to determine logic remains mostly hidden from view, instead of more spoken implicitly as an organizing feature. To understand, we need to get at the agential relationships! We must not mistake organization for productive generation.

For an analytic book, this already short book could be made tighter. Instead of hitting us quickly with the range of application, perhaps it’s better to speak simply and directly about the relationships involved and then approach the extension. In some ways, Badiou’s work on mathematics can actually be of great use here, to help outline the struggle, to give people a different method of approaching an age old question.

So in some ways, their 3 part categorization goes against answering the question “What is Philosophy” since philosophy is included as just another kind of concept. The mode that they are heading towards, but do not reach, I feel, is the deterministic view of logical apparatii, best caricatured by Bertrand Russell and Alfred North Whitehead’s Principia Mathematica in which we get the pure code of expression. Needless to say this is just another example of conceptualization, but the formalist approach, which is only one way, can help Deleuze and Guattari approach the concise outline of concept’s agency better than some of their other angles.

In a sense, the three kinds of concepts is more of a crutch for organizing their own exposition than serving to give us an understanding of the range of how concepts themselves can be extended. To that end, the conclusion feels a little strained to me, a bit too repetitious, where they reach a limit as to how to continue explaining what they have failed to outline.

View all my reviews

The Timeless Way of Building

The Timeless Way of BuildingThe Timeless Way of Building by Christopher W. Alexander
My rating: 5 of 5 stars

In this thoughtful book, Chris Alexander takes an approach to architecture that understands it through the filter of human (and non-human) agency. He understands that the most useful buildings are ones that are created by the maximization of agency of the people involved, with the utilization of language based patterns that we inhabit to organize our behavior. He writes this book almost as if talking in a dream. Reading this book is a visceral experience of stepping into the a shower.

It’s quite a masterful work, one that deals with the aesthetics of embodiedness rather than the more mundane (but necessary) considerations of budgeting, and so on. In a way, this a book of one who is entering a mastery of the craft, where the detailed considerations fall to the wayside as the considerations of that pure level of agency come into full consideration.

Alexander’s method is more meditative and thoughtful, one that seems geared towards his process of consideration and his familiarity with the “pattern languages” that he utilizes more than anything else. What I find most interesting in this book is that he utilizes spaces from other cultures all the while remarking that such patterns are built into our native language. Are they then, really more a function of our cultural-mind? He suggests we know this intuitively, and yet most people cannot build accordingly as buildings cannot be formed from a poverty of our languaged patterns. So that seems like a big epistemological-cultural hole. But at the same time, his thoughts are so compelling, you want to believe in them. That there is a potentially rich environment of knowledge and consideration that we can dig from, only if we were in tune with it!

It’s no surprise then, that he originates in the Berkeley area, as San Francisco is the hotbed of such hippy mysticism. Still, there’s something to be said for his approach and his “method” which takes a much less mechanical view of building. We should gear our use appropriately to the individuals for whom a building should embody! Our culture is impoverished due to the fragmentation of disciplines and the jealous guardians who don’t want to share with their economic competitors! In a very real way he is talking about Taoism. I look forward to reading more of his work.

View all my reviews

Computation and Cognition: Toward a Foundation for Cognitive Science

Computation and Cognition: Toward a Foundation for Cognitive ScienceComputation and Cognition: Toward a Foundation for Cognitive Science by Zenon Pylshyn
My rating: 4 of 5 stars

Zenon Pylshyn presents a strong foundation for how cognition should be literally thought in terms of: cognition. He provides a functional approach to understanding how humans can be generic thought machines. We seem to have the ability to parrot the functioning of processes themself. His later chapters in which he provides evidence in cognitive studies as to how people seem to follow a process oriented algorithm is the strongest push for this.

Having said that, looking back, it’s apparent that most of his book was simply describing the inner workings of computation and arguing that cognition needed to work on a symbolic level anyway; that the physical materialism was only the vehicle for the functionality that the functionality is what we want. In some ways I am reminded of Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell’s attempt at providing a mechanical notion of rationality. Zenon doesn’t go as far, but he wants to provide us a coherent and discrete value system upon which to weigh cognition. This isn’t a bad idea, but it appears that people don’t often make decisions on purely discrete values. We are capable of doing so, but whether or not we do so, especially outside of scientific tests, which always tests for discrete values if possible, is another matter entirely.

This is my second time reading the book. The first time was about ten years ago, and I am not sure I understood the latter parts of it. In a way, Zenon should have probably reversed the order of some of his chapters. He should have provided the cases arguing for cognition as computation with an emphasis on how cognition is process oriented based on functional equivalence, and then provided the chapters on functional architecture’s inner workings. I understand however that he was most likely providing the functional architecture first as a theoretical basis, so that we can understand what we see later on in terms of the theory…but since his book was geared towards arguing for functional architecture as the mode of consideration, it may make more sense to work towards the argument first, rather than having some cognitive proof later on as a BTW, this stuff can be explained by cognition.

In a way, what’s missing about this work is the null state of cognition. That is to say, once we get the system going with equivalences, that’s fine and good. But what mark do we make in order to start it going, where we come to identify as a self? This is perhaps troubling theory but Pylshyn does not get into this. He also seems to think that computation is the literal process of cognition. I would rather consider, in the spirit of functional architecture, that we can’t ever know what the literal process is, we can only denote equivalency in functionality. I guess that makes me fallibilist. It’s suprising that Pylshyn isn’t a fallibist, since he takes some of the question as to how memory works exactly or how processing works exactly as not being important since equivalency trumps actuality when it comes to trying to make sense of how this could work. It doesn’t matter how it works specifically, what matters is that it does in these kinds of algorithmic steps. Perhaps in this sense, this book isn’t that radical after all.

View all my reviews

Reinventing Los Angeles: Nature and Community in the Global City

Reinventing Los Angeles: Nature and Community in the Global CityReinventing Los Angeles: Nature and Community in the Global City by Robert Gottlieb
My rating: 4 of 5 stars

Robert Gottlieb considers the city of Los Angeles as the parable of the modern city. The dilemma as he draws it has to do with the conflicting social changes of technology and globalization on the cultural and natural ecologies of the city. Taking Los Angeles as a model, Gottlieb includes an astounding amount of information about Los Angeles in how it developed, changes historically and comes to embody the mixed bag of tricks it is. As a native Angelino I was fascinated by Gottliebs take on the politics and inner struggles of its class, racial and resource management groups.

The weakest part of the book is that Gottlieb splits the conclusion as a non-conclusion. His chapters are fairly strong as he picks certain events to highlight recent developments in the life of the city, particularly with the neighborhood struggles of Latinos. He isn’t however, able to cohere these into one unified vision for what Los Angeles has to overcome. When you contrast this with the strength of his understanding of the ecological struggle (anti-polluters who want to stop people from pollution vs preservationists who want to create more green spaces) you begin to get a grasp of the larger trends that characterize the struggle. When it comes to immigration, gentrification and economics, Gottlieb is a little less insightful and more “just quoting the facts”. In a way, Gottlieb could buffer this area more if he were to introduce a theoretical cut on culture the way he did on ecology.

Additionally, with recent developments in the last 5-10 years, this book could also be updated. The influx of globalization with the housing bubble crash has really hurt working class and middle class families as they are being forced out of the real estate market by outsider money. This added struggle can also help characterize the way in which large cities with their governance and their political cartels allow certain trends to develop.

All in all, not a difficult book to read. But one that was insightful. Much better than some of the other hodge podge urban studies texts that I have examined.

View all my reviews

The Consolations of Philosophy

The Consolations of PhilosophyThe Consolations of Philosophy by Alain de Botton
My rating: 3 of 5 stars

As so many other reviewers have noted, this book is a strange mixture of philosophy and self help. Like the other De Button books I’ve read, it is clear, expressive and makes a driving point. I thought it more like a cliff notes told through the personal lives of these men, more than anything else. De Button wishes to present these at times, difficult philosophers as fodder for how philosophy can be useful. In some ways its appropriate to understand that these ideas came from individuals who had to experience and embody them. In other ways its inappropriate to lessen the force of the ideas in order to humanize them (and use these figures as puppets for their thoughts). I am strangely not liking this book, but at the same time, I also find it to be an interesting and quick read.

Definitely something you can do when you are bored and want some easy distraction. I feel that his chapter on Socrates and Seneca to be the strongest. His chapter on Nietzsche and Montaigne were fairly weak, as at times these chapters seemed an aimless collection of ideas that are somehow related. So in this sense, this book is more fitting as an introduction than anything else. What makes me give it three stars even though its a light introduction is that there isn’t much consolation at all. He should have dropped the self help theme unless he wanted to end the chapters with a stronger sense of self help.

View all my reviews