« Posts under Theory

Being and Other Realities

Being and Other RealitiesBeing and Other Realities by Paul Weiss
My rating: 3 of 5 stars

Paul Weiss gives an interesting take on Being. He offers a content-level split on the domains of Being as a recognition that we cannot have a “flat” experience since so many facets of human experience today are incompossible, on different levels, that do not meet.

Nonetheless, he carries with himself a strong notion of Kantian transcendentalism as a mark on how to appropriate Rationality and Dunamis. What he calls Dunamis is simply contingency, the actualization of being itself. In a way, I think he misses a more elegant picture, one that doesn’t allow for a simple numbering of different domains through various kinds of relations, as he calls each marked by “Ultimates”: “Voluminosity, Coordinator, Affiliator, Assessor” In introducing these terms, Weiss leaves it very vague. Perhaps these are explained in past texts, but he lacks a direct explanation here, and I for one would have liked more direct talk.

It’s great that he wants to bring Being back into the world of humanity, with culture and science. In this sense, he works as a kind of heir to Heidigger. Unfortunately, wanting to say something and being too aloof to say it doesn’t help his argument. The main pull he makes that is different, I believe, to be his attempt to include agency: praxis, as one might call it. Much of what he says however is still too vague to be of use, and it’s simply a translation of what we already know about the world into the philosophic terms he wishes to utilize. In a way, I was at times embarrassed reading this book because he tries so hard to be deep, that he mystifies his relations a little too much. I don’t mind poetic language or mystification but I do not find it useful if you want people to utilize and fully embody the project as you wish to color it.

Weiss however is right, that philosophy is a deeply personal endeavor, one fraught with difficult and self revelation. A difficulty in writing a book like this is being able to effectively convey what you want to say. He doesn’t throw too much history of philosophy at you, or too much jargon, which comes at first as a relief, but very quickly becomes a failure of the book to explain itself better.

What I got out of it was merely a reinforcement of traditional philosophy as I understood it. He needs to demonstrate the feasibility of his terms more as they differentiate and influence one another. Having 4 terms named as he does doesn’t help, since he spends most of the book waxing about the different areas of human experience (nature, cosmos, individuation, culture and so on). His first chapter was very good, however.

View all my reviews

Bodies That Matter: On the Discursive Limits of “Sex”

Bodies That Matter: On the Discursive Limits of 'Sex'Bodies That Matter: On the Discursive Limits of “Sex” by Judith Butler
My rating: 5 of 5 stars

Here Judith Butler expands on the agental role that “queering” performativity allows for the creation of individuals beyond sexuality. While most of the book is geared towards shoring up (and critiquing) psychoanalytic roles of sexual determination of identity and subjectivity, Butler also includes a few complex examples of how marked positions within the sexual dichotomy as it relates to phallics and sexual identity is problematized.

Although at times with terse sentences that sometimes say too much in one bite, I feel that Butler successfully sees both sides of the issue and navigates through this minefield with a fresh outlook on how sexuality plays a role in determining how we consider ourselves and how we consider others. Using the various figures of transgender and drag and so on, Butler ultimately demonstrates that the agency relationship of performativity still requires that dichotomous hetereosexual cut. Although the performative natures of drag and trans, “queering” normative roles is always a subversive possibility, the reliance of the dichotomous hetereosexual norms as a queering always has the possibility of retroactively reinforcing rather than subverting. Put on the street, a gay pride rally may make non-normative hetereosexuals express themselves with aplomb but it will also allow conservative types to dig further into their entrenchment simply because the dichotomy is always invoked as a way of identifying who we are and where we are located.

This transcendental cut is a difficulty with queering, one that Butler does not seem able to resolve. In a way, this has to do with the fact that despite performativity’s power in one’s ability to redefine one’s self, this is always in relation to how others can define one’s self through their acts. Thus her chapter on “lesbian phallus” and the straight woman as a melancholy lesbian or the straight man as a melancholy straight man is a way to note that all positions are “queering” when we begin to eradicate the normative judgements socially and understand the relations on the sexual “phallic” transcendental as mere positional exchange. We may want to inhabit certain positions above others, and in that sense all identity is performative and “queering” when understood through alternate filters.

In a way, Butler stops in an appropriate spot. She doesn’t go too deep into critiquing transcendental reason (as obviously this would take us afar off field) but she doesn’t shy away from mentioning either, when appropriate. I feel that her ending could be tighter, as she takes a very long time to conclude where she wants to end, but she does the best that she can in outlining the fact that identity is created through sexual performativity as blind truth procedure rather than as an ontological given. She engages feminist theorists to this end in a way that is appropriate, although I feel she spends a little too much time with psychoanalysis, simply because she needs a bulwark that is hetereo-normative in order to sexualize the field in order to make her point.

The twist from ontology to procedure is really the takeaway key here, to how Butler redeploys social identity for all of us. Taken in that approach, in theory, we could have avoided sexuality all together in performativity, but the charged nature of sexuality as a key to identity allows Butler to tackle the subject all the more strongly. Bravo.

View all my reviews

The Ecology of Others

The Ecology of OthersThe Ecology of Others by Philippe Descola
My rating: 5 of 5 stars

Although a tiny book, this hits hard.

Through the field of anthropology, Descola notes the duality of nature and culture in ecology, anthropology and biology. Hard anthropology was to establish the unity of humankind. Social anthropology is meant to explain the variation within unity. This invariant cut aligns these sciences by pre-supposing an etic paradigm reflexive of a continuum of mind-body duality.

Thus, cultural is either natured by material geography or material geography is natured by culture. Either way, nature becomes a container for the limits of the study of cultural variation, either as the generator or as the mirror.

In this way, the very study of anthropology imposes a search for an invariant ontology within all cultures. For the former (cultural materialism) we look for a master generator of material reality on a soft cultural milieu. On the latter (like the idealism of Claude Levi-Strauss) we seek a master grammar of cultural semiology. Descola points out that this structuration imposes a transcendental cut that acts as a transducer. We eliminate the internal agency of the cultures that are examined, even if the ethnography is emic in search of an invariant generator that would match the hard anthropological unity that limits the study of cultural anthropology.

As a result, this duality misses the deeper implication that all cultural ageis is expressive of a human agency that operates internal to a culture, one that serves only to reproduce itself as humans reproduce ourselves. Our desire to standardize all studies is also a desire to impose our form of agency (power) on others. His suggestion then, is to study these fields as separate cuts on their own, without looking for a hard biology/material/geography or a hard idealism to calibrate variance to. In this way, he suggests we look for rules within each culture to as determining their own values and topography. In essence, he seeks the fragmentation of the field further, to find the character of each, risking our inability to speak to one another, but at the same time, discarding the value judgement we make when we attempt to normalize the difference of the other, through generative theory.

In some ways, this is expressive of a schizoanalysis (from Felix Guattari and Gilles Deleuze), to make a hetergeneology of anthropology rather than following a structuralist superstructure-account. While Descola does not go on this bend, or connect explicitly with these thinkers, his suggestion is very much to quantize anthropology, to atomize according to agency, rather than atomizing to qualities based on a supra-transcendental field of a virtual cultural generator. I do look forward to reading more of his work.

View all my reviews

The Truth of Zizek

The Truth of ZizekThe Truth of Zizek by Paul Bowman
My rating: 2 of 5 stars

I find the only thing more confusing and boring than reading Zizek (who is sometimes boring!) is reading about what academics have to say about him. Of course, this is where academia is at its most stupefying, where one can only take a stand by claiming that another did not say enough. While sometimes amusing, I think the short essays attempting to grasp Zizek’s complex and often compelling arguments seems to fall short. The problem with summing what someone says when they aren’t finished saying it, is that often we can’t figure out what kind of effect that person has had yet.

There are a few gems in this book, but it’s often undecidable as to who to give more weight to. Zizek’s 50 page reply at the end (by far the longest) encapsulates the very paragon of being himself. As he states ironically

When we are avidly expecting the new book of an author, and this book, when it finally appears, turns out to be a disappointment, we can say: ‘Although we were waiting for this book, this is not the book we were waiting for’. This, unfortunately, is also my impression apropos the texts in the present volume–not because it is highly critical of me, but because so many arguments in it are based on such a crude misreading of my position, that instead of confronting theoretical positions, I will have to spend way too much time answering insinuations and untruths as well as setting straight the misunderstandings of my position–which is, for an author, one of the most boring exercises imaginable. In order to ease this burden, I will effectively do what I am often accused of (over)doing: cut and paste bits of my past texts where I already clarified the issues debated here.

Taking the most critical stereotype of himself, Zizek gives permission for his detractors to mock him by effectively removing their ability to criticize him. He does what they claim he does so as to remove their criticism from him. In this manner, Zizek exercises in academia a general mode of reddit or 4chan or any other internet forum. You agree with your critics so they no longer have power over you. And yet, apropos Lacan (and Marx), you acknowledge the “terrestrial basis” of your ideology so that it can have greater force. We do what we do despite our intellectual cynicism because that which we do has power over us, to move us despite our skeptical, enlightened modality. In this way, Zizek may stop short of asking what his critics “hamsters” are, despite their probing into his own personal life, because as it may turn out (who knows), their critical hamsters may actually be the position they have placed Zizek himself. Perhaps (un)ironically, by questioning what his truth is, they have given him full license to continue to perpetuate the writings he engages in.

And in that sense, this book is wholly unsatisfying simply because there remains a pivoting but no synthesis of position. We are left knowing less than we knew before despite having all these experts positioned around a table differentiating themselves. I think this is a good view of academia in its meaningless repetition.

View all my reviews

Critique of Pure Reason

Critique of Pure ReasonCritique of Pure Reason by Immanuel Kant
My rating: 5 of 5 stars

So much has been written about Kant. Yes, he’s hard. He’s rammbly. He’s overbearing. But this is due in part to the fact that written in 1781, Kant did not have anyone to talk with. He lacked the ability to find other minds and interface. So in those ten years of silence he talked to himself. And he’s a bit disorganized.

So lets not quibble with the details. Instead let me cut to the heart of what he is saying, in a way that goes beyond any reading of him that I’ve come across yet.

The one aesthetic Kant is after, that allows him to hit a home run, is simply this: All concepts are regulatory.

What Kant is after is to understand the limits of what our regulatory reason can do. This can’t be a function to decide truth. This can’t be a function to decide reality. This isn’t an effort at wisdom. We can use reason to figure out the contours of contingency, of what is given to us. But we cannot use it alone to do anything.

Kant attempts to show us the value of reason in melding together different functions (be it imaginary or understanding or reason) and in this way seeks to highlight the vehicle by which we can come to grips with phenomenon. So weaknesses?

Yes, Alan Badiou is partially correct: Kant’s system requires that he created a negated structure, the noumenal upon which to hang his phenomenon. But Badiou is also partially incorrect. Kant was the first to recognize, through the figure of the transcendental, the necessity of having an apparatus of measurement upon which to solidify a phenomenal field. That is to say, phenomenon cannot interface at a consistent level unless there was a larger field to unify them as equivalent. Hence, this transcendental. Kant laid out the form for us, to quantize, to organize whatever we apperceptive. Historically, this is how Heidigger is able to note that Kant is Modernism Part II. Descartes introduces the need the for a transcendental field (in the form of the mental realm) but Kant completes his thought. Hegel is the application for this field to surject unto Absolute Knowledge.

So we miss the point when we quibble with his mathematics or his bad physics, or how he didn’t understand quantum mechanics. None of his examples matter in their detail. What matters is the principle behind this critique, one which reveals that concepts are regulatory.

And while it’s true, as Kristeva points out, Kant did not “discover” negation (leave this to Hegel as a way for him to bind according to the dialectical-synthesis process) Kant does reach negativity. Negativity is necessary as the limits for a given concept. And if you look at towards the end of this masterful work, and ignore his annoying repetition, you come to understand the antinomies are but examples of the limits of conceptualization itself.

Yes, Dedekind’s cut of real numbers or Badiou’s theory of points belie the same “cut” as Kant’s antinomies. By injecting reason in at various arbitrary positions, we can cut a dichotomy into a mass to differentiate positions. Such positions then become expressive of the cut, which we use as an absolute reference. This reference allows us to orient ourselves. So yes, when only we do not “extend reason beyond the bounds of experience” can we avoid these antinomies, Kant highlights these antinomies as way of showing how reason provides the extension of any given cut, which are always contingent by arbitrary parameters, be they a sensuous apperception or some inherited folly of the imagination. This section following The Ideal of Pure Reason all the way to the end of the work, gives us the apex of Kant’s reach. He was articulated much, but never brought it back around to exploding the limits of concepts themselves. He could only fumble and say, well, they are regulatory.

Not only are they regulatory but they are necessary for the organization, the quantization into phenomenon, inasmuch as the sensuous, as he calls it, is necessary for logic to take a stance. We need contingency to make a mark somewhere, otherwise we get nothing but pure logical presentation without any place for differentiation into a real context. It is this dual refractory nature that presents us with agential cuts to determine the nature of what is real, a mixture of contingent sensuousness and transcendental formalism. This mixture however, isn’t stable, it belies on the context of previous cuts, usually derived from our human need to have agency in limited domains.

This is the start of post-modern fragmentation of knowledge, as each domain acquires its own organizing cut.

But this is also well beyond the context of where Kant was going.

So if you keep in mind the “regulatory” nature of conceptualization, you’ll come to a fruitation that is far more radical than any reading of Kant that I’ve ever come across. I think you’ll find as well, that this radical negativity, necessary to cut concepts out of the larger folds, is why Deleuze found himself returning to Kant towards the end of his career. In this way Kant is still more radical than most anyone gives him credit for… and in this sense, his admiration for David Hume speaks volumes about where he’s going with this critique. In fact, he exceeds Hume in this way, by abstracting Hume’s explanation of human behavior as conventional habit into the modality of regulatory concepts. Kant finds the limit of reason but in doing so he is able to demonstrate how reason is utilized to supplement understanding beyond the bounds of experience. His four antinomies are but possibilities for unfounded regulations, many of which Hume would simply call “conventions”.

To wrap. I for one, am glad to have Kant as a guide. As staunch and “joyless” as he is, there is a core of clear direction within his thought that allows him to calibrate his awareness to a finely tuned point regardless of content. Kant turns rationality in on itself and is able to note the different vectors within rationality as a manifold, a field of its own connectivity. Kant adds these various example, these vectors together, rotates rationality as a vehicle of deployment and is able to find a navel limit within rationality, negativity on the one hand, sensuous apperception on the other, and the chimera of the transcendental dialectic on the third. This groundwork of pure formalism is the striking aesthetic consistency that belies German philosophy post-Kant, while marking the groundwork for the very abstract structural formalism that is to follow in mathematics and science in the 19th century and beyond. Without having the ability to negate all that does not logically follow, or being able to create limited phenomenon within a transcendental domain, we would not have any technological or mathematical achievements today.

This isn’t to say that Kant should be given credit for this because he “invented” this. Rather, he was simply the first to stake out the parameters for the nature of these kinds of endeavors, endeavors which continue to structure human experience and behavior today. No doubt, if Kant did not do this, then someone else would have formalized this exercise, eventually. Still, to one lonely man in Königsberg, thank you.

View all my reviews

Animal Liberation

Animal LiberationAnimal Liberation by Peter Singer
My rating: 5 of 5 stars

Singer takes ethics seriously. As a philosopher he provides a cut that separates the abstraction from its application. This is a compelling argument. While he shows us, in book form, much of the widely known (and unknown) atrocities that come with how we treat animals, for our gut level, animal reaction, he emphasizes that as human beings we have a choice we can make about how to be in the world. Suffering is suffering, and the cut off between human dignity and animal dignity is one that overlaps. The only difference that would block this overlap would be due to ideological weight we put on valuing humans over animals.

His argument can also rightly be distilled into various levels of agency. Eating vegetables is better for the environment, which means better for humans. Human digestion can survive without animal tissue to digest. Dignity is due to the capacity of the bearer to suffer, and animals do suffer. If we prevent the suffering of other humans due to their capacity to feel and think, there remains very little room for debate to not extend this to animals as well. Truly, our inability to extend this to animals can only be due to how we ourselves are irrational and unwilling to change our habits. Going against the grain is difficult, but if you see only a neutral situation in the face of suffering then you have chosen the side of the oppressors.

View all my reviews

The Seminar of Jacques Lacan: The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis

The Seminar of Jacques Lacan: The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis (Seminar of Jacques Lacan)The Seminar of Jacques Lacan: The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis by Jacques Lacan
My rating: 4 of 5 stars

This is my second time reading this book.

In his attempt to correct Freud, bring him up to date, Lacan approaches the same metaphysical abstraction as so many post-structuralists. A big part of psychoanalysis’s problem stems from methodology. In order to help his patients, Freud had to determine what normalcy was. And he did this through the cultural signs that were available around him. Lacan’s abstraction of these terms is an attempt to get away from the original limits of Freud and get at the principles of what Freud was talking about. The ordering that Lacan utilizes in order to center the subject is actually pretty deft. He approaches sort of sideways, from the abstraction of human desire as drive — in doing so, he places us in relation to the subject, but only from the angles at which we can see it. The distortion apparent in the subject’s view of itself, the only part where we can come to understand itself as as being — in essence, torsion in a field of the symbolic. Whether this happens through the other, or through itself, or through drive or any other conception is not as important.

What’s interesting about this difficult structure is that Lacan’s highlight follows a very familiar path. We need to have two things to measure itself against. This could be a phallic and a drive. It could be the other and its gaze. It could be the analyst and the subject. Really, there are so many available! Each of these different metrics presents for us different normalcys, different ways of sparking what may be normal. Ultimately though, Lacan is able to get us back to normalcy only when we approach the imaginary and symbolic regimes in conjunction with their phallic suture. This master signifier becomes the unit that marks the weave of meaning, in the same way that money is used as a filter in our current civilization to codify relative values.

While this is terribly interesting and a good gauge of what Lacan is talking about, what is missing in all of this psychoanalytic structure is the need for agency. We can retroactively stamp the structure onto any story or person or event we like. But we have a hard time trying to figure out how to get us back to where we need to go. The point of all this is to find out what normal is, so that we can help patients recover their sense of person, or their direction, or whatever is wrong. And that becomes a huge issue as to why psychoanalysis starts to lose its prestige today.

Of course, this is just a seminar about the conceptual framework. But shouldn’t this approach also be considered? We take this thought for granted because, I assume, we enter the seminar already believing.

View all my reviews

Modern Living Accessories: 100 Years of Design

Modern Living Accessories: 100 Years of DesignModern Living Accessories: 100 Years of Design by Martin Wellner
My rating: 4 of 5 stars

This amazing survey walks backwards into the 19th century. Year by year, you see how contemporary design evolved into its basic constituents. Modern works reflect a refinement in the use of materials, such that the deformation of familiar objects at first, geometric and blocky become expressive with a higher resolution in material agency. While many contemporary objects start to break the grey areas of design, where form suggests not only novel movements adhering to a singular force (such as Bauhaus design, where form matches function) but today into postmodern ambivalence where a singular object suggests multiple uses that are sometimes more clever than useful but at other times, far more ingenious as to dissolve the logical categories by which we classify what an object is.

Given in full page color, the short captions, and the short articles give us a brief introductory taste as to the mechanisms of design, the influence of the visions of designers and the continual mastery of material.

With the final works of the industrial revolution having established its conquest of human materialism in production, we have the beginnings of middle class wealth, to support a need for mass export of finished products. Art Deco and Art Nouveau come to the scene with its whimsical forms, to introduce a new level of finish, where product production shares no seams as to its origins. Here we have the advent of a new consumerism, the full split of producer from consumer so that only expert craftsmen and finally engineers and scientists are the gate keepers for designers. For in areas of such refinement, only the knowledge of specialized processes and the abstractness of a designers breaking out of the box lay the condition for the deformation of our modernist categories of contemporary appliances.

One thinks in the near future the inclusion of smart devices will reach a further deterritorialisation of what objects can be, do and coexist with us, further anticipating human need and modifying further the trajectory of how we can be (and have agency) in an environment.

View all my reviews

The Theory Mess: Deconstruction in Eclipse

The Theory Mess: Deconstruction in EclipseThe Theory Mess: Deconstruction in Eclipse by Herman Rapaport
My rating: 4 of 5 stars

Rapaport draws us a line from Derrida’s deconstruction as received in the United States to the foundation of critical theory. He is quick to show us how various misreadings all compound one another and contribute to the condition of loose readings and theory used for the purposes of exporting political ideology in the name of objectivity.

Rapaport is less interested in providing an analysis of the ideas involved on their own merits than with showing us how misreadings slide from a specific use of deconstruction as a philosophical movement founded on transcendental phenomenology as a basis for propelling us out of routine layers of traditional thought to the projection of social changing ideology about our roles as subjectivities. It’s useful to not misread others, but this of course does not detract from the very real condition inherent in followers of critical theory. We end up repeating routine gestures mis-attributed to thinkers like Derrida and Lacan in the name of progress. We end up constructing a new, if shortly lived tradition of post-colonialism and post-modern subjectivity in which we parrot one another with our own political teleological apparatuses.

Rapaport does however, still see deconstruction as being necessary to help bring critical theory to awareness of its own follies of structured identities and strict dualistic thinking. In a very real way, Rapaport is correct. Only a close, honest reading of the flaws of a given worldview will allow us to step beyond the constraints of our own horizons. This isn’t a promise of a new worldview, this is simply a promise of freedom, the same pursuit of freedom of thought that Derrida sought in introducing deconstruction so long ago.

View all my reviews

Alternatives: The United States Confronts the World

Alternatives: The United States Confronts the WorldAlternatives: The United States Confronts the World by Immanuel Wallerstein
My rating: 3 of 5 stars

Here, Wallerstein takes us on a take of his reactions in the critical time from 9/11 until the end of Bush’s term. While some of his predictions did not come true, about Bush not being reelected, his insightful analysis of the United States position from the view of the rest of the world was interesting.

While Wallerstein is definitely against GWB, he does allow us a rich tapestry upon which to reflect how the changing role of the United States in the world was the context in which the hawks in the US government did not recognize.

Less interesting than his own personal opinions is how he sees the relationships of politics, history and economics coming together to create a systemic basis upon which to understand the distortion of the American propaganda machine. Should we however, understand that this is propaganda? How should we understand the United States changing role? The conclusion is unclear but the trajectory is clear. We need to learn how to get along with others, after all, we are stuck in this mess together.

View all my reviews