The Enchanted Barn

The Enchanted BarnThe Enchanted Barn by Grace Livingston Hill
My rating: 3 of 5 stars

Congruent with American fiction, buildings play a role in the plot. Named after the building, the becoming of a home from a barn parallels the budding love story between a kindly but young, wealthy man and a spunky, beautiful young girl. Most of the drama lies in the young girl (and her family’s) will not to take charity from this wealthy man (and yet still doing so) but also how they don’t want him to play with her heart. And of course, he does not.

The rest of the book consists of events that work solely to draw them together as a couple. In a way, this idealized little book of relationship of the sexes from the late 1910s already shows us the model upon which American romance is to play. In that sense, the idealism of the characters is a portraiture in style. Somewhat refreshing.

View all my reviews

The Last Command

The Last Command (Star Wars: The Thrawn Trilogy, #3)The Last Command by Timothy Zahn
My rating: 3 of 5 stars

Entertaining book, although towards the end it became clear that Zahn had developed all he needed to do. The mechanisations of the middle book, through an almost mathematical reformulation of characters becomes a simple twist of the characters attempting to eek out an agential goal of some sort. What I mean is that once we know who’s side who is on, it becomes a race to see who can effect the proper technological change. This is an interesting presentation of the power of technology and the motions of politics as a modeled on material agency. In many ways this parrots Tom Clancy novels in which characters become little more than quirky personality surfaces upon which technical ability is wrapped around.

So for that reason the book, is not very surprising, and as amazing as the first two books. I did enjoy reading it however. Zahn is very easy to read. His language is clear. His dialogue is both telling and personal although by this point much of the exercise felt uninspired, as he simply had to go through the motions.

As characteristic of books with a black and white view of who we are supposed to root for, the good guys always seem to meld into an impossible level of trust. In a way, the flatness of the Leia and Luke characters from the movies comes through here in the book as a poverty of characterization. Nonetheless, his imaginative craft in writing shows via his twist in resolving the Mara Jade/Luke Skywalker episode. I saw this as both an inspired resolution AND an empty cop-out. I can’t make up my mind. In a way though, unlike the second book which really said something more than a simple character regurgitation, this volume only went through the motions to finish the story. And as such, the smuggler character felt a little tacked on, despite his prominent role in the first and second volumes. But I guess if you’ve read the first two, Zahn doesn’t need to work too hard to get you to read this one as well.

View all my reviews

Critique of Political Economy, Vol 1: The Process of Production of Capital

Capital: Critique of Political Economy, Vol 1: The Process of Production of CapitalCapital: Critique of Political Economy, Vol 1: The Process of Production of Capital by Karl Marx
My rating: 4 of 5 stars

What hasn’t been said about Capital before? The least interesting parts were the areas where Marx goes on about exploitation. This makes it very obvious that we are supposed to identify with the working class. After all, we all work for a living at something, don’t we? We all have bosses. Yet this does beg the question a little, as this sets up a self-fulfilling situation. Who is it that gets rich off of us? We don’t see them.

One of the angles that is often missed about Capital is that it is a book derived from economic principles. Marx takes it for granted that land and are production and value. He also points out that excess population will keep us poor. Land is always a problem, of course, and too many people does make a job more precious. What is happening now though, is that technology is making labor less and less important. The labor Marx spoke of is just one stage of capital. In “first world” countries we have moved mostly beyond the factory (and some farming) jobs so often cited in this book, into a different kind of economy.

It strikes me that a supplement to Capital would be to recognize that it is not capitalism that is the supreme model for civilization (producing class struggle) but it is in fact valorization and management of production/resources that produces struggle. There is also, the additional factor that class struggle is just one way to slice social antagonisms. The multitude of class and identity conflicts express themselves economically in a variety of ways that aren’t simply class, but also gender, race, religion, disability and so on. In a way, we need a more general account of social production, of which Marx showed us but only presented in a limited way.

He does however, largely through David Ricardo’s work, show us the impossible signifying bond: between exchange-value and use-value. He also is able to demonstrate how credit creates another impossible signifying bond to guarantee further exchange-value, making it a transcendental (pathological) signification. I thought that Capital would be a boring book to read. In a way, the ideas are so extended today throughout so many philosophers that, while rather long, was a snap to read.

I am told that Engels really changed the character of the book, from philosophy to a call for class uprising. I am curious as to how much this is true.

View all my reviews

A Field Guide to Getting Lost

A Field Guide to Getting LostA Field Guide to Getting Lost by Rebecca Solnit
My rating: 5 of 5 stars

Pretty amazing book. Solnit approaches “lost” as more than an epistemological concept directly outwards. She wraps this conception around itself and demonstrates through as series of vignettes, allegories and musings (personal, historical, sociological, literary) in order exemplify aspects of being lost, which includes losing being, place, direction, knowledge, feeling and familiarity.

I was terribly awed by her wide reaching “direction” as she navigates us on how to get lost, or how others did it. What’s interesting is that she doesn’t seem to lose direction either.

Rhetorically and philosophically, Solnit is able to utilize environmental decoherence to defamiliarize the centerpiece subject. The original mark in a story, which is often a person, or a direction, is waxed in different territorial contexts until you literally lose place. At that point your sense of center is gone with it. I guess what keeps you from getting lost is that Solnit is always able to keep your attention focused on what was, and what will be. Those fixed points of reference allow her to transition smoothly forward and backwards, highlighting in the process what getting lost does to a subject. Her strength of direction afforded me, the reader, to let her guide me along. Very well done.

There is a mystic sounding voice to her writing, as if a love letter (another commentator said) and if you trust that intimate tone she sets for us, the pages will swallow you whole. You’ll find time slowly disappearing in this book as you start to get lost.

Admittedly, some of the tid-bits she brings up seem strained but some of the other ones, which are well researched and well put more than make up for their weaker transitional ligamentation.

If you want to get lost in a book, ironically, this is one to do it!

View all my reviews

Against Method: Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge

Against Method: Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge Against Method: Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge by Paul Karl Feyerabend
My rating: 5 of 5 stars

Feyerabend writes a difficult book here, but one which is necessary. Taking a radically different perspective on the aesthetics of what theory is, Feyerabend attack one of the scared cows of science and mathematics — that of consistency.

In some ways, Feyerabend could have raised objections more metaphysically — that ideas have at their germination roots outside of a given domain — that culture plays a role in utilizing domains in one area to influence another — that science is a socially generated practice, on that mistakes methodology for reality — but in other ways, Feyerabend does well by sticking very close to his topic. His use of Galileo as an example is of interest, since he returns to it often but it is in his later chapters that his critique really stands out.

Basically Feyerabend shows us that knowledge is always procedural. Knowledge and theory are generated through processes of agency. By attempting to manipulate or influence a specific phenomenon, we generate procedures to gain access to that phenomenon. This requires that we calibrate our actions to an appropriate cut. Nonetheless, any cut we calibrate to is simultaneously a distortion of the very object of study, because it casts it in a certain relationship. Thus

Expressing it differently, we may say that the assumption of a single coherent world-view that underlies all of science is either a metaphysical hypothesis trying to anticipate a future unity, or a pedagogical fake; or it is an attempt to show, by a judicious up-and downgrading of disciplines, that a synthesis has already been achieved. This is how fans of uniformity proceeded in the past (cf. Plato’s lists of subjects in Chapter vii of his Republic), these are the ways that are still being used today. A more realistic account, however, would be that ‘[t]here is no simple “scientific” map of reality–or if there were, it would be much too complicated and unwieldy to be grasped or used by anyone. But there are many different maps of reality, from a variety of scientific viewpoints’

One should be quick to realize that Feyerabend is not against science at all; in fact he encourages it in his “irresponible” and “anarchist” ways. What Feyerabend is objecting to is the imagined consistency/consensus of science, a “sacred cow” of science all the more because science doesn’t need such a “petit object a” in order to function. One of the underlying criticisms that Feyerabend levels is that all social institutions (including science) are in fact first and foremost, social institutions. We understand this to be even more true when we realize that the academic/scientific community often operates as a ranking system more than as a theory generating procedure; that grants and individuals are awarded more for position than they are for work. That the entire procedure of science is one of self promotion (through the modality of whatever science they are using) more than anything else.

In some ways, Feyerabend does well to criticize past methods in order to highlight inconsistencies in how they are aestheticized and presented. But this of course, will stop no one, because past procedures are in the past. After all, aren’t we better now?

I cannot stop praising his book, because there is so much in here. I appreciate the clarity and freshness with which Feyeraband approaches this topic. On a more abstract level, one that I think Feyerabend would appreciate, is that we should approach all polemics and theories understanding that they are generated through the auspices of their own consistency and meaning. We often reject theories and ideas just like we reject people — they either don’t make the cut due to some personal inclination, or they are competitors for the same social capital. Often, these are the same thing. I whole heartedly agree with Feyerabend. With the lack of any “true” authority, one that “naturally” supersedes whatever authority we could imagine here on Earth (as there is none like that), we ought to utilize any theory that allows us to increase our agency. Should we not desire any particular agency, we should embrace any idea for what it is worth, at the time that we need it. Of course, some ideas will become undecideable should the foundation for that idea be incommensurable with our own foundation. But that is not a fault of that idea. This is merely the fault of our own localization. Sometimes, a question simply isn’t available from a given point of view because its context is not available.

This is of course, in a big way, where Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason steps in, and it is at this point that Feyerabend stops short. He doesn’t wish to get into the logistics of what is reasonable. He only wishes that we set ourselves free of the chains by which we adhere to an image of what good science ought to look like so that we can do better science. And for that, I find that there is a resonance with martial arts, or with music or any other technicality/agency. We must learn the basics to define what the modality is. From that point on, mastery begins when we start to release ourselves from technique in order to be more appropriate to whatever situation we find ourselves in, simply because technique is a pedagogical tool, and its rigid organization will make certain acts impossible because they are incommensurable with that technique.

Ultimately, consistency is how we make sense of a localization for the purposes of ordinance (organization). We must never mistake the map for the territory since the territory is always changing as our desires/designs and agential relations change — so we too change.

View all my reviews

The Paradox of Subjectivity: The Self in the Transcendental Tradition

The Paradox of Subjectivity: The Self in the Transcendental TraditionThe Paradox of Subjectivity: The Self in the Transcendental Tradition by David Carr
My rating: 5 of 5 stars

Carr presents us with an interesting puzzle, that speaks about the role of self in the transcendental tradition. In some sense, it’s not a puzzle at all. Kantian scholars often look to the point of “subjectivity” as central to Kant’s critique in inquiry. This is not so. If you read Critique of Pure Reason closely, you will see that Kants main critique is about reason itself; the way in which reason works to supplement understanding, often extending understanding beyond the bounds of what is “reasonable” for reason to speculate on.

Carr shows us at first, the bumbling that rises from the transcendental tradition. He starts off with Heidegger in order to critique him, going through Husserl and then ending later on with Kant. About halfway through we get a glimpse that the two “selves” empirical and transcendental have in fact no bearing within the tradition as a kind of truth. Rather these two points are bracketed speculations. Towards the end then, Carr, goes against the tradition of scholars that wish to push Husserl and Kant into “metaphysical” speculation, tentatively stating that

Both philosophers recognized, I think, that their transcendental procedure did not authorize the transition to metaphysical claims

And this is so! The paradox is rightly present because the scholars that follow misread and wished to pursue their own agenda of subjectivity. In this sense, this already short book, could be even shorter, as the paradox lies wholly within trying to make a round hole squared. For what Carr sets out to do, he does it quite well. Not an easy book to read, because of its heavy terminology, but it is in fact still an introductory book, although it serves as an introduction to a very complex topic.

View all my reviews

Time and Free Will: An Essay on the Immediate Data of Consciousness

Time and Free Will: An Essay on the Immediate Data of ConsciousnessTime and Free Will: An Essay on the Immediate Data of Consciousness by Henri Bergson
My rating: 4 of 5 stars

Once again, Bergson takes us in another direction. He excels at pulling out the underlying relations that structure methodology. He exposes how we construct regular notions such as time, space, self and so on — showing us that such terms are actually heterogeneous. That we assume that the formality of language and conception is what things are; ignoring the uncertainty and difference that characterizes how we consider ourselves in a constant becoming all of our own.

At the heart of this essay, Bergson takes us towards free will, understanding that our conception of selfhood as a social manifestation (so we live outside ourselves) or as an “external projection of the other” which is reached by “deep introspection” but not given to “states” that are “amenable to measure”. This suspension of our sense of being between these two regimes disallows us our freedom since we are rarely grasping ourselves and instead dealing with how we are meant to consider ourselves. This is akin to unraveling how we know ourselves; we consider who we are by slowly replacing ourselves with our own map of ourselves, and then forgetting that the map is a map, and considering the map as who we are. This insightful proposition sounds oddly postmodern but it originates for Bergson as the understanding that we are not a static field of temporal absolutes. Rather, we are a process of integration — non-repeatable and consistently in flux. It is Bergson’s criticism of philosophy and science that we ought to know ourselves by the invariance that we come to misrecognize what we are as we always eliminating contingency and difference only to assuming the inadequacy of our ideas as being static and non-changing despite the inconsistency of our lived experience… as we use our social identity (as an unchangeable reference) to anchor our physical invariance. This is also why Bergson finds fault with causality; because all points on the manifold are localizations. Extensions of localizations will never attain stability with identity.

This amounts to saying that the more we strengthen the principle of causality, the more we emphasize the difference between a physical series and a psychical one.

It is for this reason; this difference between our psychical inconsistency that is immeasurable and our “physical series” anchored in social identity that we find ourselves with free will. In essence, because we are constantly becoming- through our own sense of process and not one that is grounded on the mechanized clocks of human coordination. Bergson questions social time as being time; instead he seeks to highlight how we generate ourselves and constantly make ourselves through the immediacy of our lived contexts. Confusing this with our ordered institutions and our prized laws of equivalence and mathematical measurement would be to further alienate who we are by mistaking our tools for what we really are.

I have read quite a few of Bergson’s books by this point. I had no idea this was his doctoral thesis until I was nearly done with the book. (I tend not to read covers or jackets). In this we see the promise of Bergson’s originality; his ability to suss out difference in approach and concentrate on how the acceptance of formal invariance in method creates a context by which centralized content often doesn’t match centralized content. In many ways, this is why different disciplines cannot speak to one another; because they assume too much and do not recognize their own assumptive principles. Because, to question such principles would be, often, to destroy the very discipline those methods generate. In this, Bergson is refreshing!

View all my reviews

The Social Conquest of Earth

The Social Conquest of EarthThe Social Conquest of Earth by Edward O. Wilson
My rating: 3 of 5 stars

In this well written book, biologist Edward O Wilson would recalibrate our sense of being from individualists to a group. He notes that the balance of being human is a constant tension, one that suspends us between being too individualistic (like lone predators) and too group oriented (like ants, which are basically one individual in many bodies). He traces the development of humans as coarising with language and social development so that at a more abstract level, it’s not consciousness that develops but rather social being which develops of which consciousness is but a very localized piece.

I am not certain that Wilson gets across his aesthetic clearly. I think that if he were to speak more openly about what he is drawing, people would be off put. But by trying to maintain one foot in science, and the other in terms of the social complexity he would compare us to (ants, bees, lions), he comes fairly close. Part of our problem in understanding this eusocial view of humankind lies in how we often consider ourselves a competitors. In capitalism there is little room for community; or rather, what community does exist exists at an unconscious level. WE do the community without thinking. We follow each other, parrot each other’s gestures and copy one another linguistically, vocally, and physically as a matter of calibration.

In a way, this book reminds me of the work of the speculative work of Julian Jaynes Origin-Consciousness-Breakdown-Bicameral-Mind, although Jaynes was far more aggressive and wide reaching in his exploration of the concept than Wilson. Wilson’s main emphasis however isn’t on the science, although he is careful to always cite science at every turn. What Wilson is more after is a high level abstract vision of how to organically consider what humans are, what we do and where we would go.

I think his emphasis on Paul Gauguin is meant to emphasis this inquiry, although it gets a little lost in the light citations and various explorations in science. Obviously this is not a scientific part; the citations are not overboard. But Wilson is trying to show us that he’s not running on crazy here either. It’s a difficult balance to strike, and I am not sure that Wilson does as compelling a job as he means to. Still, this book is an interesting look at an old question, and not all that difficult to read. Worth taking a look, if the topic interests you.

View all my reviews

I am a strange loop

I Am a Strange LoopI Am a Strange Loop by Douglas R. Hofstadter
My rating: 2 of 5 stars

In I am a strange loop Douglas Hofstader asks the question, who am “I”; what is the self?

Consistent with his position as a non-jargonist, Hofstader refuses to accept domain limits on his question. Thus, Hofstader ends up at an impasse with the terms he uses (self, substance, pattern) as these terms “pull in” the domain limits that he refuses to recognize. Rather than allowing his inquiry to asymptotically approach a correct calibration to highlight the cut that outlines selfhood, (which would require that he float his terms into a new mapping), instead Hofstader insists on the reality of his non-jargon words and implicitly runs us into a kind of Kantian paradox in which on the one hand, we have an “I” of personal experience and on the other, we have only the endless repetition of patterns..

By insisting on a lack of limit in his questioning and forcing the terms he wants to apply to every context of inquiry, ironically, Hofstader’s method recreates the very answer he finds ridiculous: “Soul regression”, i.e., “inside me there is a little man who runs me; inside him there is a little man who runs him… ad infinitum”. By insisting on finding a narcissistic trace of selfhood at each level, his inquiry would have us, at every level, produce a trace of self from each domain to its sub-domain and so on.

Is this not an example of how an inquiry through its formal presentation reproduces the structure of the answer they seek? Hofstader rejects the ridiculous implications of soul regression yet he seems willing to only accept an answer that would structurally be its equivalent.

His discard of jargon in an attempt to be more “real” (good ole American pragmatism) ignores the primary fact that not-all queries can be sensible in only some domains. Looking for the self in physics is narcissistic. It’s like looking for ingredients that make a good breakfast in building code. Incidentally, this reminds me of how Kantian scholars look to critique of pure reason as a book about subjectivity, ignoring the fact that Kant’s main focus is about “pure” reason alone. Subjectivity is just another example of a transcendental chimera. Yet, I digress…

Overall, Hofstader’s book is interesting, and well written, as he explains complex ideas without the use of very technical terms. There is another way to debunk Hofstader’s reasoning however, and that’s to note what he takes for granted conceptually and what he questions. It’s of interesting to note that in many examples, Hofstader replaces nonsense terms for the very objects he questions. When questioning the veracity of mental phenomenon, he does this often. His move is to show that a lack of difference (physically) is no difference. This is silly ludicrous as he is basically transposing one term with a specific context into another domain and then demonstrating through the equivalence of nonsense terms that this object doesn’t hook into anything. This makes Hofstader a bad philosophy though, because in essence he is begging the question.

I think the main critique of this book is that if there is ever a point at which we need jargon, it’s to recognize the complex agency of those fields. Jargon words exist to express relationships that are otherwise difficult to apprehend without those jargonistic contexts. Yes, an unfortunate side effect of jargon is elitism, but that’s often the case with people who want to differentiate themselves for the purposes of status through any means necessary, so we will always have elitism, even without jargon. By removing the jargon and consideration of other kinds of logics, Hofstader limits his inquiry to a single domain, one which he recognizes as being overwhelmingly valid. This creates the same problem as mentioned before: he is looking for an answer in the wrong area. It’s like someone insisting that we find a definition for “life” in terms of building code, or trying to find a hadron in terms of biology — and upon not finding this concept expressible in the domain of their choice, concluding that this concept must be bunk all along.

I am not stating that another domain has the answer, or even a coherent answer. I am simply stating that Hofstader ties his own hands together and then through a series of very clever but limited inquiries begs the question over and over to conclude that the self does not really exist because he can’t find it present in all domains equally. What a narcissistic endeavor he has undertaken.

View all my reviews

Why Him? Why Her?: Understanding Your Personality Type and Finding the Perfect Match

Why Him? Why Her?: Understanding Your Personality Type and Finding the Perfect MatchWhy Him? Why Her?: Understanding Your Personality Type and Finding the Perfect Match by Helen Fisher
My rating: 3 of 5 stars

A self help book about love. Takes the view that neurochemicals formulate the basis for each individual’s personality type. Basic formulas of self help books follow a two step pattern. 1) establish categorical understanding. 2) apply categories to the world. This book does exactly that. Proof of this is the author’s work and statistical data she has from a match making website she consulted with. It’s possible to see people’s primary behaviors calibrated to a predominance with certain neurochemicals in their brain. But to reduce people to a mechanical agency based literally on chemistry to help us find chemistry? The packaging she puts this through appears to be very simple, straightforward and properly anecdotal. But like many self help books, there is one way to view the world (through the book) but there are also a myriad other ways to view the world. In some ways this book presents an interesting look at people, but it’s one that is perhaps too stiff to really live up to its promises. It cuts out much of the other information about why anyone and why not anyone else? If there were really as she says, 16 types, (32) given the sexes (even more given sexualities), then relationships as an art devolves into a numbers game. And at that level, we might as well all just jump into speed dating venues, in which case a guide like this doesn’t really guide us at all. In a strange way, you could even argue that this book is in some ways, advertising for the website.

But then, isn’t that always what happens with expertise, today? Experts need to make a living too. Why not do so with what they are an expert of?

View all my reviews